How can this implication be true? â$1>2 $ implies $ $ 'vegetables are healthy'.â [duplicate]
Clash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
This question already has an answer here:
In classical logic, why is $(pRightarrow q)$ True if both $p$ and $q$ are False?
20 answers
In classical logic, why is $(pRightarrow q)$ True if $p$ is False and $q$ is True?
14 answers
In mathematical logic, implication has the following truth table
where $phi$ and $ psi$ are statements, and $1$ represents true and $0$ false.
From this table, an implication such as
"$1>2 $ implies $ $ vegetables are usually healthy"
is true. (Unless, I'm mistaken.)
But surely, this implication is nonsense, so how can we even begin to talk about its veracity? Doesn't mathematical logic bother with the "meaning" behind an implication? What is the rationale behind the above truth table?
Thanks
logic first-order-logic
marked as duplicate by JMoravitz, Taroccoesbrocco, Community⦠Aug 10 at 23:14
This question has been asked before and already has an answer. If those answers do not fully address your question, please ask a new question.
 |Â
show 5 more comments
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
This question already has an answer here:
In classical logic, why is $(pRightarrow q)$ True if both $p$ and $q$ are False?
20 answers
In classical logic, why is $(pRightarrow q)$ True if $p$ is False and $q$ is True?
14 answers
In mathematical logic, implication has the following truth table
where $phi$ and $ psi$ are statements, and $1$ represents true and $0$ false.
From this table, an implication such as
"$1>2 $ implies $ $ vegetables are usually healthy"
is true. (Unless, I'm mistaken.)
But surely, this implication is nonsense, so how can we even begin to talk about its veracity? Doesn't mathematical logic bother with the "meaning" behind an implication? What is the rationale behind the above truth table?
Thanks
logic first-order-logic
marked as duplicate by JMoravitz, Taroccoesbrocco, Community⦠Aug 10 at 23:14
This question has been asked before and already has an answer. If those answers do not fully address your question, please ask a new question.
You might be interested in non-classical logic.
â Shaun
Aug 10 at 22:32
@Shaun I'll check it out - thanks.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:39
2
The result that a false premise implies anything is sometimes referred to as the Principle of explosion.
â JMoravitz
Aug 10 at 22:39
@JMoravitz I see, but what bothers me is the fact that a false statement can imply something. Is this just a convention? Shouldn't false statements imply nothing at all? as opposed to anything we want?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:48
Implication in the mathematical sense is not quite the "if-then" of the English language. As a general rule, they coincide fairly well whenever the truth value of the premise is in some way variable or uncertain, and very poorly when it is not.
â Micah
Aug 10 at 22:51
 |Â
show 5 more comments
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
This question already has an answer here:
In classical logic, why is $(pRightarrow q)$ True if both $p$ and $q$ are False?
20 answers
In classical logic, why is $(pRightarrow q)$ True if $p$ is False and $q$ is True?
14 answers
In mathematical logic, implication has the following truth table
where $phi$ and $ psi$ are statements, and $1$ represents true and $0$ false.
From this table, an implication such as
"$1>2 $ implies $ $ vegetables are usually healthy"
is true. (Unless, I'm mistaken.)
But surely, this implication is nonsense, so how can we even begin to talk about its veracity? Doesn't mathematical logic bother with the "meaning" behind an implication? What is the rationale behind the above truth table?
Thanks
logic first-order-logic
This question already has an answer here:
In classical logic, why is $(pRightarrow q)$ True if both $p$ and $q$ are False?
20 answers
In classical logic, why is $(pRightarrow q)$ True if $p$ is False and $q$ is True?
14 answers
In mathematical logic, implication has the following truth table
where $phi$ and $ psi$ are statements, and $1$ represents true and $0$ false.
From this table, an implication such as
"$1>2 $ implies $ $ vegetables are usually healthy"
is true. (Unless, I'm mistaken.)
But surely, this implication is nonsense, so how can we even begin to talk about its veracity? Doesn't mathematical logic bother with the "meaning" behind an implication? What is the rationale behind the above truth table?
Thanks
This question already has an answer here:
In classical logic, why is $(pRightarrow q)$ True if both $p$ and $q$ are False?
20 answers
In classical logic, why is $(pRightarrow q)$ True if $p$ is False and $q$ is True?
14 answers
logic first-order-logic
asked Aug 10 at 22:24
Stephen
1,2301819
1,2301819
marked as duplicate by JMoravitz, Taroccoesbrocco, Community⦠Aug 10 at 23:14
This question has been asked before and already has an answer. If those answers do not fully address your question, please ask a new question.
marked as duplicate by JMoravitz, Taroccoesbrocco, Community⦠Aug 10 at 23:14
This question has been asked before and already has an answer. If those answers do not fully address your question, please ask a new question.
You might be interested in non-classical logic.
â Shaun
Aug 10 at 22:32
@Shaun I'll check it out - thanks.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:39
2
The result that a false premise implies anything is sometimes referred to as the Principle of explosion.
â JMoravitz
Aug 10 at 22:39
@JMoravitz I see, but what bothers me is the fact that a false statement can imply something. Is this just a convention? Shouldn't false statements imply nothing at all? as opposed to anything we want?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:48
Implication in the mathematical sense is not quite the "if-then" of the English language. As a general rule, they coincide fairly well whenever the truth value of the premise is in some way variable or uncertain, and very poorly when it is not.
â Micah
Aug 10 at 22:51
 |Â
show 5 more comments
You might be interested in non-classical logic.
â Shaun
Aug 10 at 22:32
@Shaun I'll check it out - thanks.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:39
2
The result that a false premise implies anything is sometimes referred to as the Principle of explosion.
â JMoravitz
Aug 10 at 22:39
@JMoravitz I see, but what bothers me is the fact that a false statement can imply something. Is this just a convention? Shouldn't false statements imply nothing at all? as opposed to anything we want?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:48
Implication in the mathematical sense is not quite the "if-then" of the English language. As a general rule, they coincide fairly well whenever the truth value of the premise is in some way variable or uncertain, and very poorly when it is not.
â Micah
Aug 10 at 22:51
You might be interested in non-classical logic.
â Shaun
Aug 10 at 22:32
You might be interested in non-classical logic.
â Shaun
Aug 10 at 22:32
@Shaun I'll check it out - thanks.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:39
@Shaun I'll check it out - thanks.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:39
2
2
The result that a false premise implies anything is sometimes referred to as the Principle of explosion.
â JMoravitz
Aug 10 at 22:39
The result that a false premise implies anything is sometimes referred to as the Principle of explosion.
â JMoravitz
Aug 10 at 22:39
@JMoravitz I see, but what bothers me is the fact that a false statement can imply something. Is this just a convention? Shouldn't false statements imply nothing at all? as opposed to anything we want?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:48
@JMoravitz I see, but what bothers me is the fact that a false statement can imply something. Is this just a convention? Shouldn't false statements imply nothing at all? as opposed to anything we want?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:48
Implication in the mathematical sense is not quite the "if-then" of the English language. As a general rule, they coincide fairly well whenever the truth value of the premise is in some way variable or uncertain, and very poorly when it is not.
â Micah
Aug 10 at 22:51
Implication in the mathematical sense is not quite the "if-then" of the English language. As a general rule, they coincide fairly well whenever the truth value of the premise is in some way variable or uncertain, and very poorly when it is not.
â Micah
Aug 10 at 22:51
 |Â
show 5 more comments
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
up vote
4
down vote
accepted
You write (in response to a comment):
so I should be interpreting the mathematical "implication" as the definition resulting from the above truth table without trying to link it to the everyday meaning of the word implication?
I wouldn't quite go that far, but I would say that you shouldn't try too hard to make it match the natural-language behavior of implication. Rather, you should ultimately convince yourself that the truth table above is the best way to approximate natural-language implication as it is used in mathematics with a classical (= true or false) truth functional (that is, the truth value of an implication should depend only on the truth values of the hypothesis and conclusion).
To help motivate my claim above, let me give a concrete example of a situation where we definitely want a false statement to imply something:
If $104723$ divides $918273643635times 85943204812$, then either $104723$ divides $918273643635$ or $104723$ divides $85943204812$ (or both).
The crucial fact here is that $104723$ is prime, and this means that for any $a, b$, if $104723$ divides $acdot b$ then it divides either $a$ or $b$ (or both). So we can say confidently that the statement above is true, without digging into those bigger numbers' details.
But in fact we can check - with work (or a computer) - that $104723$ does not divide $918273643635cdot 85943204812$. So the hypothesis of the statement is false. At this point we're forced to conclude one of two things:
We were wrong above when we claimed that this implication held; and in particular, we can't use theorems like "If a prime divides the product of two numbers, it divides one of the numbers (or both)" in the natural way.
Or, having a false hypothesis doesn't make an implication false.
The latter is adopted for classical logic, simply because it better matches actual mathematical reasoning. You can argue that the former is better suited to natural language, and we have various nonclassical logics which try to address that, but it's important to recognize the value of being able to mathematically prove that an implication is true without showing that the hypothesis is true.
EDIT: Let me end by saying a couple words about a few other ways to approach implication.
First off, we could cook up a logic where $pimplies q$ is false whenever $p$ is false. As far as I know, this isn't done anywhere, but there's no real barrier - I just don't know that anyone's found it interesting enough to pursue (I think because "$pimplies p$" is something we pretty much all agree should be true, regardless of $p$).
However, we could try to draw a distinction between certain "vacuous" (= false-hypothesis) implications: some (like my example above, or "$1<2implies 3<4$") have a kind of logic to them, while others (like that of your title) are just ... "silly." We could demand that a vacuous implication be true only if the hypothesis is somehow "relevant" to the conclusion. In fact, once we go down this road there's no need to pay attention only to vacuous implications: something like "If $2+2=4$, then Fermat's last theorem is true" is also fishy! This leads to relevance logic (and related concepts).
Another tack we could take is to think about contingency. For example, consider the sentence "If it were raining right now, the ground outside would be wet." This is something we probably agree is true, but - at least where I am, currently - the hypothesis is false. We can resolve the situation while remaining skeptical of vacuous implications by noticing that "it is raining right now" is false but not absurd. One way of expressing this is to say that there is a possible world where it is true; there are other approaches, but I like this one at least at first. Considerations like these will ultimately lead to modal logic.
And there are others, but hopefully the above helps at first. Incidentally, if you want to dive straight into the deep end you might check out the magnifigargantuamazing book The connectives. It's $1512$ pages long - that's not a typo - and hardback, so probably not a good idea to read without close-toed shoes (you may find this review entertaining).
Another example would be equivalence of two false statements, e.g. $1<2 iff 2<3$. We can get each statement by either adding or subtracting $1$ from the other statement on both sides, which should be an operation that doesn't change the validity.
â Sellerie
Aug 10 at 23:03
@Sellerie True, but I'm not sure that would be as convincing to the OP; I wanted to pick an implication that is obviously true and apparently meaningful. But you're quite right.
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:03
1
Very helpful, thanks. The examples you gave make total sense, and indeed illustrates quite well why we have such a definition, and also how to think about them.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 23:22
add a comment |Â
up vote
3
down vote
You can think of it more like "whenever $phi$ is true, $psi$ must also be true". Then it becomes clear that any false statement implies every other statement, no matter if true or false, since the "whenever" part never actually applies.
add a comment |Â
up vote
0
down vote
That is because any false assertion implies whatever you want, since you cannot find a counter-example, i.e. an example with the assertion true and the conclusion false.
If $phi$ is false, then indeed we can't find a case in which it's veracity implies a false statement, agreed. But, this is not satisfying. Instead of saying a false statement implies anything, isn't it more factual to say that a false statement does not imply anything at all?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:38
1
@Stephen No, it isn't. Classical logic actually models rather decently standard mathematical reasoning. You want it to model natural language, and find it wanting. In a sense, that is not entirely surprising, since really this was not the goal. Luckily, we now have a large array of nonclassical logics that serve as alternatives.
â Andrés E. Caicedo
Aug 10 at 22:49
1
@Stephen I think it's natural at the very least to assert that a false statement implies itself ...
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:05
add a comment |Â
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
up vote
4
down vote
accepted
You write (in response to a comment):
so I should be interpreting the mathematical "implication" as the definition resulting from the above truth table without trying to link it to the everyday meaning of the word implication?
I wouldn't quite go that far, but I would say that you shouldn't try too hard to make it match the natural-language behavior of implication. Rather, you should ultimately convince yourself that the truth table above is the best way to approximate natural-language implication as it is used in mathematics with a classical (= true or false) truth functional (that is, the truth value of an implication should depend only on the truth values of the hypothesis and conclusion).
To help motivate my claim above, let me give a concrete example of a situation where we definitely want a false statement to imply something:
If $104723$ divides $918273643635times 85943204812$, then either $104723$ divides $918273643635$ or $104723$ divides $85943204812$ (or both).
The crucial fact here is that $104723$ is prime, and this means that for any $a, b$, if $104723$ divides $acdot b$ then it divides either $a$ or $b$ (or both). So we can say confidently that the statement above is true, without digging into those bigger numbers' details.
But in fact we can check - with work (or a computer) - that $104723$ does not divide $918273643635cdot 85943204812$. So the hypothesis of the statement is false. At this point we're forced to conclude one of two things:
We were wrong above when we claimed that this implication held; and in particular, we can't use theorems like "If a prime divides the product of two numbers, it divides one of the numbers (or both)" in the natural way.
Or, having a false hypothesis doesn't make an implication false.
The latter is adopted for classical logic, simply because it better matches actual mathematical reasoning. You can argue that the former is better suited to natural language, and we have various nonclassical logics which try to address that, but it's important to recognize the value of being able to mathematically prove that an implication is true without showing that the hypothesis is true.
EDIT: Let me end by saying a couple words about a few other ways to approach implication.
First off, we could cook up a logic where $pimplies q$ is false whenever $p$ is false. As far as I know, this isn't done anywhere, but there's no real barrier - I just don't know that anyone's found it interesting enough to pursue (I think because "$pimplies p$" is something we pretty much all agree should be true, regardless of $p$).
However, we could try to draw a distinction between certain "vacuous" (= false-hypothesis) implications: some (like my example above, or "$1<2implies 3<4$") have a kind of logic to them, while others (like that of your title) are just ... "silly." We could demand that a vacuous implication be true only if the hypothesis is somehow "relevant" to the conclusion. In fact, once we go down this road there's no need to pay attention only to vacuous implications: something like "If $2+2=4$, then Fermat's last theorem is true" is also fishy! This leads to relevance logic (and related concepts).
Another tack we could take is to think about contingency. For example, consider the sentence "If it were raining right now, the ground outside would be wet." This is something we probably agree is true, but - at least where I am, currently - the hypothesis is false. We can resolve the situation while remaining skeptical of vacuous implications by noticing that "it is raining right now" is false but not absurd. One way of expressing this is to say that there is a possible world where it is true; there are other approaches, but I like this one at least at first. Considerations like these will ultimately lead to modal logic.
And there are others, but hopefully the above helps at first. Incidentally, if you want to dive straight into the deep end you might check out the magnifigargantuamazing book The connectives. It's $1512$ pages long - that's not a typo - and hardback, so probably not a good idea to read without close-toed shoes (you may find this review entertaining).
Another example would be equivalence of two false statements, e.g. $1<2 iff 2<3$. We can get each statement by either adding or subtracting $1$ from the other statement on both sides, which should be an operation that doesn't change the validity.
â Sellerie
Aug 10 at 23:03
@Sellerie True, but I'm not sure that would be as convincing to the OP; I wanted to pick an implication that is obviously true and apparently meaningful. But you're quite right.
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:03
1
Very helpful, thanks. The examples you gave make total sense, and indeed illustrates quite well why we have such a definition, and also how to think about them.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 23:22
add a comment |Â
up vote
4
down vote
accepted
You write (in response to a comment):
so I should be interpreting the mathematical "implication" as the definition resulting from the above truth table without trying to link it to the everyday meaning of the word implication?
I wouldn't quite go that far, but I would say that you shouldn't try too hard to make it match the natural-language behavior of implication. Rather, you should ultimately convince yourself that the truth table above is the best way to approximate natural-language implication as it is used in mathematics with a classical (= true or false) truth functional (that is, the truth value of an implication should depend only on the truth values of the hypothesis and conclusion).
To help motivate my claim above, let me give a concrete example of a situation where we definitely want a false statement to imply something:
If $104723$ divides $918273643635times 85943204812$, then either $104723$ divides $918273643635$ or $104723$ divides $85943204812$ (or both).
The crucial fact here is that $104723$ is prime, and this means that for any $a, b$, if $104723$ divides $acdot b$ then it divides either $a$ or $b$ (or both). So we can say confidently that the statement above is true, without digging into those bigger numbers' details.
But in fact we can check - with work (or a computer) - that $104723$ does not divide $918273643635cdot 85943204812$. So the hypothesis of the statement is false. At this point we're forced to conclude one of two things:
We were wrong above when we claimed that this implication held; and in particular, we can't use theorems like "If a prime divides the product of two numbers, it divides one of the numbers (or both)" in the natural way.
Or, having a false hypothesis doesn't make an implication false.
The latter is adopted for classical logic, simply because it better matches actual mathematical reasoning. You can argue that the former is better suited to natural language, and we have various nonclassical logics which try to address that, but it's important to recognize the value of being able to mathematically prove that an implication is true without showing that the hypothesis is true.
EDIT: Let me end by saying a couple words about a few other ways to approach implication.
First off, we could cook up a logic where $pimplies q$ is false whenever $p$ is false. As far as I know, this isn't done anywhere, but there's no real barrier - I just don't know that anyone's found it interesting enough to pursue (I think because "$pimplies p$" is something we pretty much all agree should be true, regardless of $p$).
However, we could try to draw a distinction between certain "vacuous" (= false-hypothesis) implications: some (like my example above, or "$1<2implies 3<4$") have a kind of logic to them, while others (like that of your title) are just ... "silly." We could demand that a vacuous implication be true only if the hypothesis is somehow "relevant" to the conclusion. In fact, once we go down this road there's no need to pay attention only to vacuous implications: something like "If $2+2=4$, then Fermat's last theorem is true" is also fishy! This leads to relevance logic (and related concepts).
Another tack we could take is to think about contingency. For example, consider the sentence "If it were raining right now, the ground outside would be wet." This is something we probably agree is true, but - at least where I am, currently - the hypothesis is false. We can resolve the situation while remaining skeptical of vacuous implications by noticing that "it is raining right now" is false but not absurd. One way of expressing this is to say that there is a possible world where it is true; there are other approaches, but I like this one at least at first. Considerations like these will ultimately lead to modal logic.
And there are others, but hopefully the above helps at first. Incidentally, if you want to dive straight into the deep end you might check out the magnifigargantuamazing book The connectives. It's $1512$ pages long - that's not a typo - and hardback, so probably not a good idea to read without close-toed shoes (you may find this review entertaining).
Another example would be equivalence of two false statements, e.g. $1<2 iff 2<3$. We can get each statement by either adding or subtracting $1$ from the other statement on both sides, which should be an operation that doesn't change the validity.
â Sellerie
Aug 10 at 23:03
@Sellerie True, but I'm not sure that would be as convincing to the OP; I wanted to pick an implication that is obviously true and apparently meaningful. But you're quite right.
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:03
1
Very helpful, thanks. The examples you gave make total sense, and indeed illustrates quite well why we have such a definition, and also how to think about them.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 23:22
add a comment |Â
up vote
4
down vote
accepted
up vote
4
down vote
accepted
You write (in response to a comment):
so I should be interpreting the mathematical "implication" as the definition resulting from the above truth table without trying to link it to the everyday meaning of the word implication?
I wouldn't quite go that far, but I would say that you shouldn't try too hard to make it match the natural-language behavior of implication. Rather, you should ultimately convince yourself that the truth table above is the best way to approximate natural-language implication as it is used in mathematics with a classical (= true or false) truth functional (that is, the truth value of an implication should depend only on the truth values of the hypothesis and conclusion).
To help motivate my claim above, let me give a concrete example of a situation where we definitely want a false statement to imply something:
If $104723$ divides $918273643635times 85943204812$, then either $104723$ divides $918273643635$ or $104723$ divides $85943204812$ (or both).
The crucial fact here is that $104723$ is prime, and this means that for any $a, b$, if $104723$ divides $acdot b$ then it divides either $a$ or $b$ (or both). So we can say confidently that the statement above is true, without digging into those bigger numbers' details.
But in fact we can check - with work (or a computer) - that $104723$ does not divide $918273643635cdot 85943204812$. So the hypothesis of the statement is false. At this point we're forced to conclude one of two things:
We were wrong above when we claimed that this implication held; and in particular, we can't use theorems like "If a prime divides the product of two numbers, it divides one of the numbers (or both)" in the natural way.
Or, having a false hypothesis doesn't make an implication false.
The latter is adopted for classical logic, simply because it better matches actual mathematical reasoning. You can argue that the former is better suited to natural language, and we have various nonclassical logics which try to address that, but it's important to recognize the value of being able to mathematically prove that an implication is true without showing that the hypothesis is true.
EDIT: Let me end by saying a couple words about a few other ways to approach implication.
First off, we could cook up a logic where $pimplies q$ is false whenever $p$ is false. As far as I know, this isn't done anywhere, but there's no real barrier - I just don't know that anyone's found it interesting enough to pursue (I think because "$pimplies p$" is something we pretty much all agree should be true, regardless of $p$).
However, we could try to draw a distinction between certain "vacuous" (= false-hypothesis) implications: some (like my example above, or "$1<2implies 3<4$") have a kind of logic to them, while others (like that of your title) are just ... "silly." We could demand that a vacuous implication be true only if the hypothesis is somehow "relevant" to the conclusion. In fact, once we go down this road there's no need to pay attention only to vacuous implications: something like "If $2+2=4$, then Fermat's last theorem is true" is also fishy! This leads to relevance logic (and related concepts).
Another tack we could take is to think about contingency. For example, consider the sentence "If it were raining right now, the ground outside would be wet." This is something we probably agree is true, but - at least where I am, currently - the hypothesis is false. We can resolve the situation while remaining skeptical of vacuous implications by noticing that "it is raining right now" is false but not absurd. One way of expressing this is to say that there is a possible world where it is true; there are other approaches, but I like this one at least at first. Considerations like these will ultimately lead to modal logic.
And there are others, but hopefully the above helps at first. Incidentally, if you want to dive straight into the deep end you might check out the magnifigargantuamazing book The connectives. It's $1512$ pages long - that's not a typo - and hardback, so probably not a good idea to read without close-toed shoes (you may find this review entertaining).
You write (in response to a comment):
so I should be interpreting the mathematical "implication" as the definition resulting from the above truth table without trying to link it to the everyday meaning of the word implication?
I wouldn't quite go that far, but I would say that you shouldn't try too hard to make it match the natural-language behavior of implication. Rather, you should ultimately convince yourself that the truth table above is the best way to approximate natural-language implication as it is used in mathematics with a classical (= true or false) truth functional (that is, the truth value of an implication should depend only on the truth values of the hypothesis and conclusion).
To help motivate my claim above, let me give a concrete example of a situation where we definitely want a false statement to imply something:
If $104723$ divides $918273643635times 85943204812$, then either $104723$ divides $918273643635$ or $104723$ divides $85943204812$ (or both).
The crucial fact here is that $104723$ is prime, and this means that for any $a, b$, if $104723$ divides $acdot b$ then it divides either $a$ or $b$ (or both). So we can say confidently that the statement above is true, without digging into those bigger numbers' details.
But in fact we can check - with work (or a computer) - that $104723$ does not divide $918273643635cdot 85943204812$. So the hypothesis of the statement is false. At this point we're forced to conclude one of two things:
We were wrong above when we claimed that this implication held; and in particular, we can't use theorems like "If a prime divides the product of two numbers, it divides one of the numbers (or both)" in the natural way.
Or, having a false hypothesis doesn't make an implication false.
The latter is adopted for classical logic, simply because it better matches actual mathematical reasoning. You can argue that the former is better suited to natural language, and we have various nonclassical logics which try to address that, but it's important to recognize the value of being able to mathematically prove that an implication is true without showing that the hypothesis is true.
EDIT: Let me end by saying a couple words about a few other ways to approach implication.
First off, we could cook up a logic where $pimplies q$ is false whenever $p$ is false. As far as I know, this isn't done anywhere, but there's no real barrier - I just don't know that anyone's found it interesting enough to pursue (I think because "$pimplies p$" is something we pretty much all agree should be true, regardless of $p$).
However, we could try to draw a distinction between certain "vacuous" (= false-hypothesis) implications: some (like my example above, or "$1<2implies 3<4$") have a kind of logic to them, while others (like that of your title) are just ... "silly." We could demand that a vacuous implication be true only if the hypothesis is somehow "relevant" to the conclusion. In fact, once we go down this road there's no need to pay attention only to vacuous implications: something like "If $2+2=4$, then Fermat's last theorem is true" is also fishy! This leads to relevance logic (and related concepts).
Another tack we could take is to think about contingency. For example, consider the sentence "If it were raining right now, the ground outside would be wet." This is something we probably agree is true, but - at least where I am, currently - the hypothesis is false. We can resolve the situation while remaining skeptical of vacuous implications by noticing that "it is raining right now" is false but not absurd. One way of expressing this is to say that there is a possible world where it is true; there are other approaches, but I like this one at least at first. Considerations like these will ultimately lead to modal logic.
And there are others, but hopefully the above helps at first. Incidentally, if you want to dive straight into the deep end you might check out the magnifigargantuamazing book The connectives. It's $1512$ pages long - that's not a typo - and hardback, so probably not a good idea to read without close-toed shoes (you may find this review entertaining).
edited Aug 10 at 23:20
answered Aug 10 at 22:56
Noah Schweber
111k9140264
111k9140264
Another example would be equivalence of two false statements, e.g. $1<2 iff 2<3$. We can get each statement by either adding or subtracting $1$ from the other statement on both sides, which should be an operation that doesn't change the validity.
â Sellerie
Aug 10 at 23:03
@Sellerie True, but I'm not sure that would be as convincing to the OP; I wanted to pick an implication that is obviously true and apparently meaningful. But you're quite right.
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:03
1
Very helpful, thanks. The examples you gave make total sense, and indeed illustrates quite well why we have such a definition, and also how to think about them.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 23:22
add a comment |Â
Another example would be equivalence of two false statements, e.g. $1<2 iff 2<3$. We can get each statement by either adding or subtracting $1$ from the other statement on both sides, which should be an operation that doesn't change the validity.
â Sellerie
Aug 10 at 23:03
@Sellerie True, but I'm not sure that would be as convincing to the OP; I wanted to pick an implication that is obviously true and apparently meaningful. But you're quite right.
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:03
1
Very helpful, thanks. The examples you gave make total sense, and indeed illustrates quite well why we have such a definition, and also how to think about them.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 23:22
Another example would be equivalence of two false statements, e.g. $1<2 iff 2<3$. We can get each statement by either adding or subtracting $1$ from the other statement on both sides, which should be an operation that doesn't change the validity.
â Sellerie
Aug 10 at 23:03
Another example would be equivalence of two false statements, e.g. $1<2 iff 2<3$. We can get each statement by either adding or subtracting $1$ from the other statement on both sides, which should be an operation that doesn't change the validity.
â Sellerie
Aug 10 at 23:03
@Sellerie True, but I'm not sure that would be as convincing to the OP; I wanted to pick an implication that is obviously true and apparently meaningful. But you're quite right.
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:03
@Sellerie True, but I'm not sure that would be as convincing to the OP; I wanted to pick an implication that is obviously true and apparently meaningful. But you're quite right.
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:03
1
1
Very helpful, thanks. The examples you gave make total sense, and indeed illustrates quite well why we have such a definition, and also how to think about them.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 23:22
Very helpful, thanks. The examples you gave make total sense, and indeed illustrates quite well why we have such a definition, and also how to think about them.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 23:22
add a comment |Â
up vote
3
down vote
You can think of it more like "whenever $phi$ is true, $psi$ must also be true". Then it becomes clear that any false statement implies every other statement, no matter if true or false, since the "whenever" part never actually applies.
add a comment |Â
up vote
3
down vote
You can think of it more like "whenever $phi$ is true, $psi$ must also be true". Then it becomes clear that any false statement implies every other statement, no matter if true or false, since the "whenever" part never actually applies.
add a comment |Â
up vote
3
down vote
up vote
3
down vote
You can think of it more like "whenever $phi$ is true, $psi$ must also be true". Then it becomes clear that any false statement implies every other statement, no matter if true or false, since the "whenever" part never actually applies.
You can think of it more like "whenever $phi$ is true, $psi$ must also be true". Then it becomes clear that any false statement implies every other statement, no matter if true or false, since the "whenever" part never actually applies.
answered Aug 10 at 22:34
Sellerie
738
738
add a comment |Â
add a comment |Â
up vote
0
down vote
That is because any false assertion implies whatever you want, since you cannot find a counter-example, i.e. an example with the assertion true and the conclusion false.
If $phi$ is false, then indeed we can't find a case in which it's veracity implies a false statement, agreed. But, this is not satisfying. Instead of saying a false statement implies anything, isn't it more factual to say that a false statement does not imply anything at all?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:38
1
@Stephen No, it isn't. Classical logic actually models rather decently standard mathematical reasoning. You want it to model natural language, and find it wanting. In a sense, that is not entirely surprising, since really this was not the goal. Luckily, we now have a large array of nonclassical logics that serve as alternatives.
â Andrés E. Caicedo
Aug 10 at 22:49
1
@Stephen I think it's natural at the very least to assert that a false statement implies itself ...
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:05
add a comment |Â
up vote
0
down vote
That is because any false assertion implies whatever you want, since you cannot find a counter-example, i.e. an example with the assertion true and the conclusion false.
If $phi$ is false, then indeed we can't find a case in which it's veracity implies a false statement, agreed. But, this is not satisfying. Instead of saying a false statement implies anything, isn't it more factual to say that a false statement does not imply anything at all?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:38
1
@Stephen No, it isn't. Classical logic actually models rather decently standard mathematical reasoning. You want it to model natural language, and find it wanting. In a sense, that is not entirely surprising, since really this was not the goal. Luckily, we now have a large array of nonclassical logics that serve as alternatives.
â Andrés E. Caicedo
Aug 10 at 22:49
1
@Stephen I think it's natural at the very least to assert that a false statement implies itself ...
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:05
add a comment |Â
up vote
0
down vote
up vote
0
down vote
That is because any false assertion implies whatever you want, since you cannot find a counter-example, i.e. an example with the assertion true and the conclusion false.
That is because any false assertion implies whatever you want, since you cannot find a counter-example, i.e. an example with the assertion true and the conclusion false.
answered Aug 10 at 22:27
Bernard
111k635103
111k635103
If $phi$ is false, then indeed we can't find a case in which it's veracity implies a false statement, agreed. But, this is not satisfying. Instead of saying a false statement implies anything, isn't it more factual to say that a false statement does not imply anything at all?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:38
1
@Stephen No, it isn't. Classical logic actually models rather decently standard mathematical reasoning. You want it to model natural language, and find it wanting. In a sense, that is not entirely surprising, since really this was not the goal. Luckily, we now have a large array of nonclassical logics that serve as alternatives.
â Andrés E. Caicedo
Aug 10 at 22:49
1
@Stephen I think it's natural at the very least to assert that a false statement implies itself ...
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:05
add a comment |Â
If $phi$ is false, then indeed we can't find a case in which it's veracity implies a false statement, agreed. But, this is not satisfying. Instead of saying a false statement implies anything, isn't it more factual to say that a false statement does not imply anything at all?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:38
1
@Stephen No, it isn't. Classical logic actually models rather decently standard mathematical reasoning. You want it to model natural language, and find it wanting. In a sense, that is not entirely surprising, since really this was not the goal. Luckily, we now have a large array of nonclassical logics that serve as alternatives.
â Andrés E. Caicedo
Aug 10 at 22:49
1
@Stephen I think it's natural at the very least to assert that a false statement implies itself ...
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:05
If $phi$ is false, then indeed we can't find a case in which it's veracity implies a false statement, agreed. But, this is not satisfying. Instead of saying a false statement implies anything, isn't it more factual to say that a false statement does not imply anything at all?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:38
If $phi$ is false, then indeed we can't find a case in which it's veracity implies a false statement, agreed. But, this is not satisfying. Instead of saying a false statement implies anything, isn't it more factual to say that a false statement does not imply anything at all?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:38
1
1
@Stephen No, it isn't. Classical logic actually models rather decently standard mathematical reasoning. You want it to model natural language, and find it wanting. In a sense, that is not entirely surprising, since really this was not the goal. Luckily, we now have a large array of nonclassical logics that serve as alternatives.
â Andrés E. Caicedo
Aug 10 at 22:49
@Stephen No, it isn't. Classical logic actually models rather decently standard mathematical reasoning. You want it to model natural language, and find it wanting. In a sense, that is not entirely surprising, since really this was not the goal. Luckily, we now have a large array of nonclassical logics that serve as alternatives.
â Andrés E. Caicedo
Aug 10 at 22:49
1
1
@Stephen I think it's natural at the very least to assert that a false statement implies itself ...
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:05
@Stephen I think it's natural at the very least to assert that a false statement implies itself ...
â Noah Schweber
Aug 10 at 23:05
add a comment |Â
You might be interested in non-classical logic.
â Shaun
Aug 10 at 22:32
@Shaun I'll check it out - thanks.
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:39
2
The result that a false premise implies anything is sometimes referred to as the Principle of explosion.
â JMoravitz
Aug 10 at 22:39
@JMoravitz I see, but what bothers me is the fact that a false statement can imply something. Is this just a convention? Shouldn't false statements imply nothing at all? as opposed to anything we want?
â Stephen
Aug 10 at 22:48
Implication in the mathematical sense is not quite the "if-then" of the English language. As a general rule, they coincide fairly well whenever the truth value of the premise is in some way variable or uncertain, and very poorly when it is not.
â Micah
Aug 10 at 22:51