Extending a Filter in a Well-Ordered Boolean Algebra to an Ultrafilter WITHOUT the Axiom of Choice
Clash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP
up vote
1
down vote
favorite
Hypothesis: Let $B$ be a well-ordered boolean algebra and let $F subseteq B$ be a filter on $B$.
Goal: Show that $F$ can be extended to an ultrafilter without the axiom of choice (or any equivalent notion thereof).
I only know how to do this in the case that $B$ is countable:
Let $b_0, b_1, ldots$ denote the countable elements of $B$.
Let $0$ denote the minimal element of $B$.
Then $0 notin F$ and if $U$ is an ultrafilter on $B$ then $0 notin U$.
Now begin extending $F$ to $F_1, F_2, ldots , F_k, ldots$ by inducting on the members of $B = b_0, b_1, ldots$ as follows:
Inductive Step: Suppose $b_k notin F_k-1$. If $b_k cdot a = 0$ for any $a in F_k-1$, then let $F_k = F_k-1 cup barb_k$. Otherwise, let $F_k = F_k-1 cup b_k$.
Letting $U = bigcup_k = 1^infty F_k$ gives us an ultrafilter extension of $F$ s.t. $U subseteq B$ as desired. Furthermore, we did not use the axiom of choice.
But what happens if $B$ is uncountable (but still well-ordered)? Evidently it's still possible to show.
logic boolean-algebra axiom-of-choice filters
add a comment |Â
up vote
1
down vote
favorite
Hypothesis: Let $B$ be a well-ordered boolean algebra and let $F subseteq B$ be a filter on $B$.
Goal: Show that $F$ can be extended to an ultrafilter without the axiom of choice (or any equivalent notion thereof).
I only know how to do this in the case that $B$ is countable:
Let $b_0, b_1, ldots$ denote the countable elements of $B$.
Let $0$ denote the minimal element of $B$.
Then $0 notin F$ and if $U$ is an ultrafilter on $B$ then $0 notin U$.
Now begin extending $F$ to $F_1, F_2, ldots , F_k, ldots$ by inducting on the members of $B = b_0, b_1, ldots$ as follows:
Inductive Step: Suppose $b_k notin F_k-1$. If $b_k cdot a = 0$ for any $a in F_k-1$, then let $F_k = F_k-1 cup barb_k$. Otherwise, let $F_k = F_k-1 cup b_k$.
Letting $U = bigcup_k = 1^infty F_k$ gives us an ultrafilter extension of $F$ s.t. $U subseteq B$ as desired. Furthermore, we did not use the axiom of choice.
But what happens if $B$ is uncountable (but still well-ordered)? Evidently it's still possible to show.
logic boolean-algebra axiom-of-choice filters
add a comment |Â
up vote
1
down vote
favorite
up vote
1
down vote
favorite
Hypothesis: Let $B$ be a well-ordered boolean algebra and let $F subseteq B$ be a filter on $B$.
Goal: Show that $F$ can be extended to an ultrafilter without the axiom of choice (or any equivalent notion thereof).
I only know how to do this in the case that $B$ is countable:
Let $b_0, b_1, ldots$ denote the countable elements of $B$.
Let $0$ denote the minimal element of $B$.
Then $0 notin F$ and if $U$ is an ultrafilter on $B$ then $0 notin U$.
Now begin extending $F$ to $F_1, F_2, ldots , F_k, ldots$ by inducting on the members of $B = b_0, b_1, ldots$ as follows:
Inductive Step: Suppose $b_k notin F_k-1$. If $b_k cdot a = 0$ for any $a in F_k-1$, then let $F_k = F_k-1 cup barb_k$. Otherwise, let $F_k = F_k-1 cup b_k$.
Letting $U = bigcup_k = 1^infty F_k$ gives us an ultrafilter extension of $F$ s.t. $U subseteq B$ as desired. Furthermore, we did not use the axiom of choice.
But what happens if $B$ is uncountable (but still well-ordered)? Evidently it's still possible to show.
logic boolean-algebra axiom-of-choice filters
Hypothesis: Let $B$ be a well-ordered boolean algebra and let $F subseteq B$ be a filter on $B$.
Goal: Show that $F$ can be extended to an ultrafilter without the axiom of choice (or any equivalent notion thereof).
I only know how to do this in the case that $B$ is countable:
Let $b_0, b_1, ldots$ denote the countable elements of $B$.
Let $0$ denote the minimal element of $B$.
Then $0 notin F$ and if $U$ is an ultrafilter on $B$ then $0 notin U$.
Now begin extending $F$ to $F_1, F_2, ldots , F_k, ldots$ by inducting on the members of $B = b_0, b_1, ldots$ as follows:
Inductive Step: Suppose $b_k notin F_k-1$. If $b_k cdot a = 0$ for any $a in F_k-1$, then let $F_k = F_k-1 cup barb_k$. Otherwise, let $F_k = F_k-1 cup b_k$.
Letting $U = bigcup_k = 1^infty F_k$ gives us an ultrafilter extension of $F$ s.t. $U subseteq B$ as desired. Furthermore, we did not use the axiom of choice.
But what happens if $B$ is uncountable (but still well-ordered)? Evidently it's still possible to show.
logic boolean-algebra axiom-of-choice filters
logic boolean-algebra axiom-of-choice filters
edited Sep 1 at 3:56
Eric Wofsey
166k12196308
166k12196308
asked Oct 26 '13 at 2:16
user1770201
1,32221134
1,32221134
add a comment |Â
add a comment |Â
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
up vote
6
down vote
accepted
The proof of the general case is similar, proceeding to define a filter by transfinite recursion rather than by recursion on $mathbbN$. (I am using "recursion" to refer to a method of defining a sequence, and "induction" to refer to a method of proving that every element of the sequence has some desired property such as the finite intersection property.)
If $B$ is well-ordered then we can enumerate its elements as $B = b_alpha : alpha < kappa$ for some ordinal $kappa$. The successor step of the recursive definition is the same as in the countable case $kappa = omega$, although in any case I think you only want to put the new element $b_alpha$ into $F_alpha+1$ if $b_alpha cdot a_0 cdots a_n-1 ne 0$ for every finite subset $a_0,ldots,a_n-1 subset F_alpha$, so as to preserve the finite intersection property.
The new ingredient in the proof is the limit step. If we want to define $F_lambda$ where $lambda < kappa$ is a limit ordinal, then we may assume as our inductive hypothesis that we have defined $F_alpha$ at all previous steps $alpha < lambda$ and that these $F_alpha$'s form an increasing chain under inclusion. Then we simply set $F_lambda = bigcup_alpha < lambda F_alpha$ and observe that the finite intersection property is preserved under unions of chains.
Remark: It might be possible to define the ultrafilter more directly from the well-ordering using some trick. For example, given a well-ordered vector space one can define a basis for that space simply by taking all vectors that are not in the span of the vectors preceding them in the well-ordering. I don't know if there is a similar trick that would work here, but in any case the advantage of transfinite recursion is that it provides straightforward solutions to a large variety of problems once you know the basics of the method.
I'm a bit confused with your notation. In particular, why is that we can write $B = b_alpha : alpha < kappa$? What exactly does that mean? The way I'm reading is "$B$ has some cardinality" -- but I'm sure that's not what you're meaning here.
â user1770201
Oct 26 '13 at 10:08
@user1770201 Given a cardinal (or just an ordinal) $kappa$ and a bijection (or just a surjection) $f:kappa to B$, we can write $B = f(alpha) : alpha < kappa$. Because $alpha < kappa$ means the same thing as $alpha in kappa$, this just says that $B$ is the range of $f$. Finally, we can denote $f(alpha)$ by the more suggestive notation $b_alpha$. We can think of $b_alpha : alpha < kappa$ as an enumeration of the elements of $B$ in $kappa$ many steps.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:18
@user1770201 Probably the confusing part (except for set theorists) is that for ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$ the notation $alpha < beta$ means the same thing as the notation $alpha in beta$. All of the instances of "$<$" in the answer could be changed to "$in$" but I'm not sure whether this would make it clearer.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:21
You meant to write "for some ordinal $kappa$". Otherwise, without axiom of choice, there might be many cardinals which are not represented by ordinals, in which case the convention that cardinals are just initial ordinals isn't all that great, and the notation $alpha<kappa$ doesn't even make sense.
â tomasz
Oct 26 '13 at 21:51
@tomasz By cardinal I always mean "initial ordinal," even though, as you say, it may not be a great convention. In any case $kappa$ in this particular situation is the cardinalty of $B$, which is assumed to be well-ordered.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 21:56
 |Â
show 2 more comments
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
up vote
6
down vote
accepted
The proof of the general case is similar, proceeding to define a filter by transfinite recursion rather than by recursion on $mathbbN$. (I am using "recursion" to refer to a method of defining a sequence, and "induction" to refer to a method of proving that every element of the sequence has some desired property such as the finite intersection property.)
If $B$ is well-ordered then we can enumerate its elements as $B = b_alpha : alpha < kappa$ for some ordinal $kappa$. The successor step of the recursive definition is the same as in the countable case $kappa = omega$, although in any case I think you only want to put the new element $b_alpha$ into $F_alpha+1$ if $b_alpha cdot a_0 cdots a_n-1 ne 0$ for every finite subset $a_0,ldots,a_n-1 subset F_alpha$, so as to preserve the finite intersection property.
The new ingredient in the proof is the limit step. If we want to define $F_lambda$ where $lambda < kappa$ is a limit ordinal, then we may assume as our inductive hypothesis that we have defined $F_alpha$ at all previous steps $alpha < lambda$ and that these $F_alpha$'s form an increasing chain under inclusion. Then we simply set $F_lambda = bigcup_alpha < lambda F_alpha$ and observe that the finite intersection property is preserved under unions of chains.
Remark: It might be possible to define the ultrafilter more directly from the well-ordering using some trick. For example, given a well-ordered vector space one can define a basis for that space simply by taking all vectors that are not in the span of the vectors preceding them in the well-ordering. I don't know if there is a similar trick that would work here, but in any case the advantage of transfinite recursion is that it provides straightforward solutions to a large variety of problems once you know the basics of the method.
I'm a bit confused with your notation. In particular, why is that we can write $B = b_alpha : alpha < kappa$? What exactly does that mean? The way I'm reading is "$B$ has some cardinality" -- but I'm sure that's not what you're meaning here.
â user1770201
Oct 26 '13 at 10:08
@user1770201 Given a cardinal (or just an ordinal) $kappa$ and a bijection (or just a surjection) $f:kappa to B$, we can write $B = f(alpha) : alpha < kappa$. Because $alpha < kappa$ means the same thing as $alpha in kappa$, this just says that $B$ is the range of $f$. Finally, we can denote $f(alpha)$ by the more suggestive notation $b_alpha$. We can think of $b_alpha : alpha < kappa$ as an enumeration of the elements of $B$ in $kappa$ many steps.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:18
@user1770201 Probably the confusing part (except for set theorists) is that for ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$ the notation $alpha < beta$ means the same thing as the notation $alpha in beta$. All of the instances of "$<$" in the answer could be changed to "$in$" but I'm not sure whether this would make it clearer.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:21
You meant to write "for some ordinal $kappa$". Otherwise, without axiom of choice, there might be many cardinals which are not represented by ordinals, in which case the convention that cardinals are just initial ordinals isn't all that great, and the notation $alpha<kappa$ doesn't even make sense.
â tomasz
Oct 26 '13 at 21:51
@tomasz By cardinal I always mean "initial ordinal," even though, as you say, it may not be a great convention. In any case $kappa$ in this particular situation is the cardinalty of $B$, which is assumed to be well-ordered.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 21:56
 |Â
show 2 more comments
up vote
6
down vote
accepted
The proof of the general case is similar, proceeding to define a filter by transfinite recursion rather than by recursion on $mathbbN$. (I am using "recursion" to refer to a method of defining a sequence, and "induction" to refer to a method of proving that every element of the sequence has some desired property such as the finite intersection property.)
If $B$ is well-ordered then we can enumerate its elements as $B = b_alpha : alpha < kappa$ for some ordinal $kappa$. The successor step of the recursive definition is the same as in the countable case $kappa = omega$, although in any case I think you only want to put the new element $b_alpha$ into $F_alpha+1$ if $b_alpha cdot a_0 cdots a_n-1 ne 0$ for every finite subset $a_0,ldots,a_n-1 subset F_alpha$, so as to preserve the finite intersection property.
The new ingredient in the proof is the limit step. If we want to define $F_lambda$ where $lambda < kappa$ is a limit ordinal, then we may assume as our inductive hypothesis that we have defined $F_alpha$ at all previous steps $alpha < lambda$ and that these $F_alpha$'s form an increasing chain under inclusion. Then we simply set $F_lambda = bigcup_alpha < lambda F_alpha$ and observe that the finite intersection property is preserved under unions of chains.
Remark: It might be possible to define the ultrafilter more directly from the well-ordering using some trick. For example, given a well-ordered vector space one can define a basis for that space simply by taking all vectors that are not in the span of the vectors preceding them in the well-ordering. I don't know if there is a similar trick that would work here, but in any case the advantage of transfinite recursion is that it provides straightforward solutions to a large variety of problems once you know the basics of the method.
I'm a bit confused with your notation. In particular, why is that we can write $B = b_alpha : alpha < kappa$? What exactly does that mean? The way I'm reading is "$B$ has some cardinality" -- but I'm sure that's not what you're meaning here.
â user1770201
Oct 26 '13 at 10:08
@user1770201 Given a cardinal (or just an ordinal) $kappa$ and a bijection (or just a surjection) $f:kappa to B$, we can write $B = f(alpha) : alpha < kappa$. Because $alpha < kappa$ means the same thing as $alpha in kappa$, this just says that $B$ is the range of $f$. Finally, we can denote $f(alpha)$ by the more suggestive notation $b_alpha$. We can think of $b_alpha : alpha < kappa$ as an enumeration of the elements of $B$ in $kappa$ many steps.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:18
@user1770201 Probably the confusing part (except for set theorists) is that for ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$ the notation $alpha < beta$ means the same thing as the notation $alpha in beta$. All of the instances of "$<$" in the answer could be changed to "$in$" but I'm not sure whether this would make it clearer.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:21
You meant to write "for some ordinal $kappa$". Otherwise, without axiom of choice, there might be many cardinals which are not represented by ordinals, in which case the convention that cardinals are just initial ordinals isn't all that great, and the notation $alpha<kappa$ doesn't even make sense.
â tomasz
Oct 26 '13 at 21:51
@tomasz By cardinal I always mean "initial ordinal," even though, as you say, it may not be a great convention. In any case $kappa$ in this particular situation is the cardinalty of $B$, which is assumed to be well-ordered.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 21:56
 |Â
show 2 more comments
up vote
6
down vote
accepted
up vote
6
down vote
accepted
The proof of the general case is similar, proceeding to define a filter by transfinite recursion rather than by recursion on $mathbbN$. (I am using "recursion" to refer to a method of defining a sequence, and "induction" to refer to a method of proving that every element of the sequence has some desired property such as the finite intersection property.)
If $B$ is well-ordered then we can enumerate its elements as $B = b_alpha : alpha < kappa$ for some ordinal $kappa$. The successor step of the recursive definition is the same as in the countable case $kappa = omega$, although in any case I think you only want to put the new element $b_alpha$ into $F_alpha+1$ if $b_alpha cdot a_0 cdots a_n-1 ne 0$ for every finite subset $a_0,ldots,a_n-1 subset F_alpha$, so as to preserve the finite intersection property.
The new ingredient in the proof is the limit step. If we want to define $F_lambda$ where $lambda < kappa$ is a limit ordinal, then we may assume as our inductive hypothesis that we have defined $F_alpha$ at all previous steps $alpha < lambda$ and that these $F_alpha$'s form an increasing chain under inclusion. Then we simply set $F_lambda = bigcup_alpha < lambda F_alpha$ and observe that the finite intersection property is preserved under unions of chains.
Remark: It might be possible to define the ultrafilter more directly from the well-ordering using some trick. For example, given a well-ordered vector space one can define a basis for that space simply by taking all vectors that are not in the span of the vectors preceding them in the well-ordering. I don't know if there is a similar trick that would work here, but in any case the advantage of transfinite recursion is that it provides straightforward solutions to a large variety of problems once you know the basics of the method.
The proof of the general case is similar, proceeding to define a filter by transfinite recursion rather than by recursion on $mathbbN$. (I am using "recursion" to refer to a method of defining a sequence, and "induction" to refer to a method of proving that every element of the sequence has some desired property such as the finite intersection property.)
If $B$ is well-ordered then we can enumerate its elements as $B = b_alpha : alpha < kappa$ for some ordinal $kappa$. The successor step of the recursive definition is the same as in the countable case $kappa = omega$, although in any case I think you only want to put the new element $b_alpha$ into $F_alpha+1$ if $b_alpha cdot a_0 cdots a_n-1 ne 0$ for every finite subset $a_0,ldots,a_n-1 subset F_alpha$, so as to preserve the finite intersection property.
The new ingredient in the proof is the limit step. If we want to define $F_lambda$ where $lambda < kappa$ is a limit ordinal, then we may assume as our inductive hypothesis that we have defined $F_alpha$ at all previous steps $alpha < lambda$ and that these $F_alpha$'s form an increasing chain under inclusion. Then we simply set $F_lambda = bigcup_alpha < lambda F_alpha$ and observe that the finite intersection property is preserved under unions of chains.
Remark: It might be possible to define the ultrafilter more directly from the well-ordering using some trick. For example, given a well-ordered vector space one can define a basis for that space simply by taking all vectors that are not in the span of the vectors preceding them in the well-ordering. I don't know if there is a similar trick that would work here, but in any case the advantage of transfinite recursion is that it provides straightforward solutions to a large variety of problems once you know the basics of the method.
edited Oct 26 '13 at 22:16
answered Oct 26 '13 at 3:02
Trevor Wilson
14.6k2456
14.6k2456
I'm a bit confused with your notation. In particular, why is that we can write $B = b_alpha : alpha < kappa$? What exactly does that mean? The way I'm reading is "$B$ has some cardinality" -- but I'm sure that's not what you're meaning here.
â user1770201
Oct 26 '13 at 10:08
@user1770201 Given a cardinal (or just an ordinal) $kappa$ and a bijection (or just a surjection) $f:kappa to B$, we can write $B = f(alpha) : alpha < kappa$. Because $alpha < kappa$ means the same thing as $alpha in kappa$, this just says that $B$ is the range of $f$. Finally, we can denote $f(alpha)$ by the more suggestive notation $b_alpha$. We can think of $b_alpha : alpha < kappa$ as an enumeration of the elements of $B$ in $kappa$ many steps.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:18
@user1770201 Probably the confusing part (except for set theorists) is that for ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$ the notation $alpha < beta$ means the same thing as the notation $alpha in beta$. All of the instances of "$<$" in the answer could be changed to "$in$" but I'm not sure whether this would make it clearer.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:21
You meant to write "for some ordinal $kappa$". Otherwise, without axiom of choice, there might be many cardinals which are not represented by ordinals, in which case the convention that cardinals are just initial ordinals isn't all that great, and the notation $alpha<kappa$ doesn't even make sense.
â tomasz
Oct 26 '13 at 21:51
@tomasz By cardinal I always mean "initial ordinal," even though, as you say, it may not be a great convention. In any case $kappa$ in this particular situation is the cardinalty of $B$, which is assumed to be well-ordered.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 21:56
 |Â
show 2 more comments
I'm a bit confused with your notation. In particular, why is that we can write $B = b_alpha : alpha < kappa$? What exactly does that mean? The way I'm reading is "$B$ has some cardinality" -- but I'm sure that's not what you're meaning here.
â user1770201
Oct 26 '13 at 10:08
@user1770201 Given a cardinal (or just an ordinal) $kappa$ and a bijection (or just a surjection) $f:kappa to B$, we can write $B = f(alpha) : alpha < kappa$. Because $alpha < kappa$ means the same thing as $alpha in kappa$, this just says that $B$ is the range of $f$. Finally, we can denote $f(alpha)$ by the more suggestive notation $b_alpha$. We can think of $b_alpha : alpha < kappa$ as an enumeration of the elements of $B$ in $kappa$ many steps.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:18
@user1770201 Probably the confusing part (except for set theorists) is that for ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$ the notation $alpha < beta$ means the same thing as the notation $alpha in beta$. All of the instances of "$<$" in the answer could be changed to "$in$" but I'm not sure whether this would make it clearer.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:21
You meant to write "for some ordinal $kappa$". Otherwise, without axiom of choice, there might be many cardinals which are not represented by ordinals, in which case the convention that cardinals are just initial ordinals isn't all that great, and the notation $alpha<kappa$ doesn't even make sense.
â tomasz
Oct 26 '13 at 21:51
@tomasz By cardinal I always mean "initial ordinal," even though, as you say, it may not be a great convention. In any case $kappa$ in this particular situation is the cardinalty of $B$, which is assumed to be well-ordered.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 21:56
I'm a bit confused with your notation. In particular, why is that we can write $B = b_alpha : alpha < kappa$? What exactly does that mean? The way I'm reading is "$B$ has some cardinality" -- but I'm sure that's not what you're meaning here.
â user1770201
Oct 26 '13 at 10:08
I'm a bit confused with your notation. In particular, why is that we can write $B = b_alpha : alpha < kappa$? What exactly does that mean? The way I'm reading is "$B$ has some cardinality" -- but I'm sure that's not what you're meaning here.
â user1770201
Oct 26 '13 at 10:08
@user1770201 Given a cardinal (or just an ordinal) $kappa$ and a bijection (or just a surjection) $f:kappa to B$, we can write $B = f(alpha) : alpha < kappa$. Because $alpha < kappa$ means the same thing as $alpha in kappa$, this just says that $B$ is the range of $f$. Finally, we can denote $f(alpha)$ by the more suggestive notation $b_alpha$. We can think of $b_alpha : alpha < kappa$ as an enumeration of the elements of $B$ in $kappa$ many steps.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:18
@user1770201 Given a cardinal (or just an ordinal) $kappa$ and a bijection (or just a surjection) $f:kappa to B$, we can write $B = f(alpha) : alpha < kappa$. Because $alpha < kappa$ means the same thing as $alpha in kappa$, this just says that $B$ is the range of $f$. Finally, we can denote $f(alpha)$ by the more suggestive notation $b_alpha$. We can think of $b_alpha : alpha < kappa$ as an enumeration of the elements of $B$ in $kappa$ many steps.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:18
@user1770201 Probably the confusing part (except for set theorists) is that for ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$ the notation $alpha < beta$ means the same thing as the notation $alpha in beta$. All of the instances of "$<$" in the answer could be changed to "$in$" but I'm not sure whether this would make it clearer.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:21
@user1770201 Probably the confusing part (except for set theorists) is that for ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$ the notation $alpha < beta$ means the same thing as the notation $alpha in beta$. All of the instances of "$<$" in the answer could be changed to "$in$" but I'm not sure whether this would make it clearer.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 17:21
You meant to write "for some ordinal $kappa$". Otherwise, without axiom of choice, there might be many cardinals which are not represented by ordinals, in which case the convention that cardinals are just initial ordinals isn't all that great, and the notation $alpha<kappa$ doesn't even make sense.
â tomasz
Oct 26 '13 at 21:51
You meant to write "for some ordinal $kappa$". Otherwise, without axiom of choice, there might be many cardinals which are not represented by ordinals, in which case the convention that cardinals are just initial ordinals isn't all that great, and the notation $alpha<kappa$ doesn't even make sense.
â tomasz
Oct 26 '13 at 21:51
@tomasz By cardinal I always mean "initial ordinal," even though, as you say, it may not be a great convention. In any case $kappa$ in this particular situation is the cardinalty of $B$, which is assumed to be well-ordered.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 21:56
@tomasz By cardinal I always mean "initial ordinal," even though, as you say, it may not be a great convention. In any case $kappa$ in this particular situation is the cardinalty of $B$, which is assumed to be well-ordered.
â Trevor Wilson
Oct 26 '13 at 21:56
 |Â
show 2 more comments
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f539896%2fextending-a-filter-in-a-well-ordered-boolean-algebra-to-an-ultrafilter-without-t%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password