Construction of arbitrary regular polygons with ruler and compass
Clash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
A lot of arithmetic geometry has to do and took off with constructions or proofs of non-constructibility of specific figures only with ruler and compass. See e.g. the non-constructibility of the regular heptagon and the constructibility of the regular heptadecagon by Gauss.
I wonder what it means that there is a simple device that can be constructed with the help of a ruler and a compass that together with ruler and compass allows to construct arbitrary regular polygons very easily.
The device is nothing but a solid cone of finite height and a flexible
string of length smaller than the circumference of the cone.
Now arrange $n$ dots on the string at equal distances and close the string such that also the first and the last dot have the same distance. I.e. you arrange $n$ dots equally on a closed string. This can be achieved with a compass alone.
After that you place the string on the cone, keeping all dots at same height until they all touch the cone. Projecting them vertically on the plane gives the corners of a regular $n$-gon.
Note that the cone is not a magic device like the angle trisector which may help to construct a rectangular heptagon, but adds nothing genuinely new to ruler and compass (because it can be constructed with the help of these). On the other hand, a flexible string is enough to create a ruler (as a physical device), and you need two rulers to make a compass. So a string might be enough for everything, in a specific sense? Note further, that angle trisectors - and more generally angle $k$-sectors - can easily be constructed for any angle $alpha = 2pi / n$: just place $kn$ dots on the string.
My question is:
Is there something wrong with my device? Might it be not constructible
with the help of ruler and compass alone? Do other parts of the
described procedure add something else beyond ruler and compass (the
cone itself is supposed not to)?
I guess, it's leaving the plane that "disqualifies" this kind of construction. Might this have to do with leaving the real number line and entering the complex plane when solving polynomial equations? ("Suddenly all polynomial equations can be solved!") On the other hand: The compass is a genuinely three-dimensional device, too!
[Counter-historical note: If geometers would not have restricted themselves (deliberately?) to ruler and compass, there would have been no necessity to study the constructibilty of regular $n$-gons - and lots of arithmetic might not have been discovered (or only considerably later). On the other side: Wouldn't complex numbers have been discovered earlier, when the cone device had been considered more seriously?]
euclidean-geometry math-history geometric-construction arithmetic-geometry
 |Â
show 2 more comments
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
A lot of arithmetic geometry has to do and took off with constructions or proofs of non-constructibility of specific figures only with ruler and compass. See e.g. the non-constructibility of the regular heptagon and the constructibility of the regular heptadecagon by Gauss.
I wonder what it means that there is a simple device that can be constructed with the help of a ruler and a compass that together with ruler and compass allows to construct arbitrary regular polygons very easily.
The device is nothing but a solid cone of finite height and a flexible
string of length smaller than the circumference of the cone.
Now arrange $n$ dots on the string at equal distances and close the string such that also the first and the last dot have the same distance. I.e. you arrange $n$ dots equally on a closed string. This can be achieved with a compass alone.
After that you place the string on the cone, keeping all dots at same height until they all touch the cone. Projecting them vertically on the plane gives the corners of a regular $n$-gon.
Note that the cone is not a magic device like the angle trisector which may help to construct a rectangular heptagon, but adds nothing genuinely new to ruler and compass (because it can be constructed with the help of these). On the other hand, a flexible string is enough to create a ruler (as a physical device), and you need two rulers to make a compass. So a string might be enough for everything, in a specific sense? Note further, that angle trisectors - and more generally angle $k$-sectors - can easily be constructed for any angle $alpha = 2pi / n$: just place $kn$ dots on the string.
My question is:
Is there something wrong with my device? Might it be not constructible
with the help of ruler and compass alone? Do other parts of the
described procedure add something else beyond ruler and compass (the
cone itself is supposed not to)?
I guess, it's leaving the plane that "disqualifies" this kind of construction. Might this have to do with leaving the real number line and entering the complex plane when solving polynomial equations? ("Suddenly all polynomial equations can be solved!") On the other hand: The compass is a genuinely three-dimensional device, too!
[Counter-historical note: If geometers would not have restricted themselves (deliberately?) to ruler and compass, there would have been no necessity to study the constructibilty of regular $n$-gons - and lots of arithmetic might not have been discovered (or only considerably later). On the other side: Wouldn't complex numbers have been discovered earlier, when the cone device had been considered more seriously?]
euclidean-geometry math-history geometric-construction arithmetic-geometry
How do you project vertically with compass and ruler? Is plane construction through a point perpendicular to another plane a known thing?
â dEmigOd
Aug 21 at 10:27
That's the kind of objections I was asking for. One could use the light of the sun (at least the ancient Greeks could have come upon this).
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:32
If you are talking about light of the sun, then should not beams be actually not parallel, nor gravitational pull, as it supposed to be directed to the center of the earth.
â dEmigOd
Aug 21 at 10:42
1
You can also do things with a marked ruler that compass and straightedge are not able to. -- Even though you can certainly draw a picture of the marked ruler with a straightedge, that does not count as a "compass and straightedge" construction.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 10:46
@dEmigOd: The greeks - when they were to think about it - would most surely have assumed, that the light of the sun comes in parallel.
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:54
 |Â
show 2 more comments
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
A lot of arithmetic geometry has to do and took off with constructions or proofs of non-constructibility of specific figures only with ruler and compass. See e.g. the non-constructibility of the regular heptagon and the constructibility of the regular heptadecagon by Gauss.
I wonder what it means that there is a simple device that can be constructed with the help of a ruler and a compass that together with ruler and compass allows to construct arbitrary regular polygons very easily.
The device is nothing but a solid cone of finite height and a flexible
string of length smaller than the circumference of the cone.
Now arrange $n$ dots on the string at equal distances and close the string such that also the first and the last dot have the same distance. I.e. you arrange $n$ dots equally on a closed string. This can be achieved with a compass alone.
After that you place the string on the cone, keeping all dots at same height until they all touch the cone. Projecting them vertically on the plane gives the corners of a regular $n$-gon.
Note that the cone is not a magic device like the angle trisector which may help to construct a rectangular heptagon, but adds nothing genuinely new to ruler and compass (because it can be constructed with the help of these). On the other hand, a flexible string is enough to create a ruler (as a physical device), and you need two rulers to make a compass. So a string might be enough for everything, in a specific sense? Note further, that angle trisectors - and more generally angle $k$-sectors - can easily be constructed for any angle $alpha = 2pi / n$: just place $kn$ dots on the string.
My question is:
Is there something wrong with my device? Might it be not constructible
with the help of ruler and compass alone? Do other parts of the
described procedure add something else beyond ruler and compass (the
cone itself is supposed not to)?
I guess, it's leaving the plane that "disqualifies" this kind of construction. Might this have to do with leaving the real number line and entering the complex plane when solving polynomial equations? ("Suddenly all polynomial equations can be solved!") On the other hand: The compass is a genuinely three-dimensional device, too!
[Counter-historical note: If geometers would not have restricted themselves (deliberately?) to ruler and compass, there would have been no necessity to study the constructibilty of regular $n$-gons - and lots of arithmetic might not have been discovered (or only considerably later). On the other side: Wouldn't complex numbers have been discovered earlier, when the cone device had been considered more seriously?]
euclidean-geometry math-history geometric-construction arithmetic-geometry
A lot of arithmetic geometry has to do and took off with constructions or proofs of non-constructibility of specific figures only with ruler and compass. See e.g. the non-constructibility of the regular heptagon and the constructibility of the regular heptadecagon by Gauss.
I wonder what it means that there is a simple device that can be constructed with the help of a ruler and a compass that together with ruler and compass allows to construct arbitrary regular polygons very easily.
The device is nothing but a solid cone of finite height and a flexible
string of length smaller than the circumference of the cone.
Now arrange $n$ dots on the string at equal distances and close the string such that also the first and the last dot have the same distance. I.e. you arrange $n$ dots equally on a closed string. This can be achieved with a compass alone.
After that you place the string on the cone, keeping all dots at same height until they all touch the cone. Projecting them vertically on the plane gives the corners of a regular $n$-gon.
Note that the cone is not a magic device like the angle trisector which may help to construct a rectangular heptagon, but adds nothing genuinely new to ruler and compass (because it can be constructed with the help of these). On the other hand, a flexible string is enough to create a ruler (as a physical device), and you need two rulers to make a compass. So a string might be enough for everything, in a specific sense? Note further, that angle trisectors - and more generally angle $k$-sectors - can easily be constructed for any angle $alpha = 2pi / n$: just place $kn$ dots on the string.
My question is:
Is there something wrong with my device? Might it be not constructible
with the help of ruler and compass alone? Do other parts of the
described procedure add something else beyond ruler and compass (the
cone itself is supposed not to)?
I guess, it's leaving the plane that "disqualifies" this kind of construction. Might this have to do with leaving the real number line and entering the complex plane when solving polynomial equations? ("Suddenly all polynomial equations can be solved!") On the other hand: The compass is a genuinely three-dimensional device, too!
[Counter-historical note: If geometers would not have restricted themselves (deliberately?) to ruler and compass, there would have been no necessity to study the constructibilty of regular $n$-gons - and lots of arithmetic might not have been discovered (or only considerably later). On the other side: Wouldn't complex numbers have been discovered earlier, when the cone device had been considered more seriously?]
euclidean-geometry math-history geometric-construction arithmetic-geometry
edited Aug 21 at 10:19
asked Aug 21 at 9:58
Hans Stricker
4,34513574
4,34513574
How do you project vertically with compass and ruler? Is plane construction through a point perpendicular to another plane a known thing?
â dEmigOd
Aug 21 at 10:27
That's the kind of objections I was asking for. One could use the light of the sun (at least the ancient Greeks could have come upon this).
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:32
If you are talking about light of the sun, then should not beams be actually not parallel, nor gravitational pull, as it supposed to be directed to the center of the earth.
â dEmigOd
Aug 21 at 10:42
1
You can also do things with a marked ruler that compass and straightedge are not able to. -- Even though you can certainly draw a picture of the marked ruler with a straightedge, that does not count as a "compass and straightedge" construction.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 10:46
@dEmigOd: The greeks - when they were to think about it - would most surely have assumed, that the light of the sun comes in parallel.
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:54
 |Â
show 2 more comments
How do you project vertically with compass and ruler? Is plane construction through a point perpendicular to another plane a known thing?
â dEmigOd
Aug 21 at 10:27
That's the kind of objections I was asking for. One could use the light of the sun (at least the ancient Greeks could have come upon this).
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:32
If you are talking about light of the sun, then should not beams be actually not parallel, nor gravitational pull, as it supposed to be directed to the center of the earth.
â dEmigOd
Aug 21 at 10:42
1
You can also do things with a marked ruler that compass and straightedge are not able to. -- Even though you can certainly draw a picture of the marked ruler with a straightedge, that does not count as a "compass and straightedge" construction.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 10:46
@dEmigOd: The greeks - when they were to think about it - would most surely have assumed, that the light of the sun comes in parallel.
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:54
How do you project vertically with compass and ruler? Is plane construction through a point perpendicular to another plane a known thing?
â dEmigOd
Aug 21 at 10:27
How do you project vertically with compass and ruler? Is plane construction through a point perpendicular to another plane a known thing?
â dEmigOd
Aug 21 at 10:27
That's the kind of objections I was asking for. One could use the light of the sun (at least the ancient Greeks could have come upon this).
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:32
That's the kind of objections I was asking for. One could use the light of the sun (at least the ancient Greeks could have come upon this).
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:32
If you are talking about light of the sun, then should not beams be actually not parallel, nor gravitational pull, as it supposed to be directed to the center of the earth.
â dEmigOd
Aug 21 at 10:42
If you are talking about light of the sun, then should not beams be actually not parallel, nor gravitational pull, as it supposed to be directed to the center of the earth.
â dEmigOd
Aug 21 at 10:42
1
1
You can also do things with a marked ruler that compass and straightedge are not able to. -- Even though you can certainly draw a picture of the marked ruler with a straightedge, that does not count as a "compass and straightedge" construction.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 10:46
You can also do things with a marked ruler that compass and straightedge are not able to. -- Even though you can certainly draw a picture of the marked ruler with a straightedge, that does not count as a "compass and straightedge" construction.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 10:46
@dEmigOd: The greeks - when they were to think about it - would most surely have assumed, that the light of the sun comes in parallel.
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:54
@dEmigOd: The greeks - when they were to think about it - would most surely have assumed, that the light of the sun comes in parallel.
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:54
 |Â
show 2 more comments
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
up vote
2
down vote
The basic misunderstanding here is that "ruler and compass" is not really about which physical tools you're allowed to use.
When this phrase appears in mathematics it is a shorthand reference to the idea of basing constructions on the three first postulates of Book I of Euclid's Elements:
To draw a straight line from any point to any point.
To produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight line.
To describe a circle with any center and radius.
(The fourth and fifth postulates are not basic constructions but are claims about what happens when certain other combinations of constructions are performed).
These three postulates are the definition of "ruler and compass". Often in English the alternative phrase "compass and straightedge" is preferred, to underscore the fact that there is none of the basic allowed constructions that depend depend on having measuring marks on your ruler.
In fact even without leaving the two-dimensional paper there are things you can imagine doing with a ruler that has measuring marks on it -- so-called neusis constructions. These are nevertheless not part of the basic operations. They can, for example, be used to trisect angles.
Mathematics is not about physical tools. Saying "ruler and compass" is merely supposed to remind you what the fundamental three constructions in Euclid are. You may, if you wish, object that it is a confusing or misleading shorthand -- that is ultimately a subjective judgment -- but this does not change the fact that what we really care about is not the tools named by the shorthand, but the three postulates it attempts to point to.
What does "continuously" in the second postulate mean, BTW. What would happen if we dropped "continuously"?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:12
Let me repeat my question: Might it be the case that we need a marked ruler to create a cone? (Even though you might be saying that this doesn't matter.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:13
@HansStricker: I'm not sure whether "continuously" has any real content here, except perhaps to point out that the original finite straight line together with its extension is supposed to form a single straight line rather than a curve that has a bend where you started extending it. The quotation is from an English translation of the Greek original text, and Euclid was not quite up to today's standard of precision particularly in his basic definitions.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 11:21
To be sure: "straightedge and compass" doesn't allow to draw equidistant marks on the straightedge with the compass (resulting in a marked ruler)? I.e. we may draw a two-dimensional circle in the plane but not a one-dimensional circle on the ruler? We are allowed to do the more complicated but not the more simple? Or do I miss the point?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:48
To sum it up: The straight edge has to be thought of as a beam of light (in which we cannot make marks). We must not think of it as a straight physical body. But how may we think of the compass? Doesn't it have to be a physical body with a definite length? (Nevertheless, Euclidean geometry is about drawing.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 12:07
 |Â
show 8 more comments
up vote
0
down vote
That's actually very clever! It shows that the ruler and compass model may actually be narrow-minded, since flexible strings are available, as is paper.
However, I believe that if flexible things are not allowed, then we still have unconstructability proofs. For instance, suppose everything we cut out is solid. Then we are only allowed to place it on the plane, and everything we get will have been constructed in the plane before cutting out the shape. So only if we are allowed to bend and stretch things, the third dimension gives additional possibilities.
What could you do without flexibel strings (or let's say flexible rulers)? How would you measure the length of the circumference of a circle? (This is what you must do: 1. Draw a circle on a piece of wood. 2. Cut it out perfectly. 3. Lay the flexibel ruler around it. 4. Create a straight ruler of equal length.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:57
add a comment |Â
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
up vote
2
down vote
The basic misunderstanding here is that "ruler and compass" is not really about which physical tools you're allowed to use.
When this phrase appears in mathematics it is a shorthand reference to the idea of basing constructions on the three first postulates of Book I of Euclid's Elements:
To draw a straight line from any point to any point.
To produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight line.
To describe a circle with any center and radius.
(The fourth and fifth postulates are not basic constructions but are claims about what happens when certain other combinations of constructions are performed).
These three postulates are the definition of "ruler and compass". Often in English the alternative phrase "compass and straightedge" is preferred, to underscore the fact that there is none of the basic allowed constructions that depend depend on having measuring marks on your ruler.
In fact even without leaving the two-dimensional paper there are things you can imagine doing with a ruler that has measuring marks on it -- so-called neusis constructions. These are nevertheless not part of the basic operations. They can, for example, be used to trisect angles.
Mathematics is not about physical tools. Saying "ruler and compass" is merely supposed to remind you what the fundamental three constructions in Euclid are. You may, if you wish, object that it is a confusing or misleading shorthand -- that is ultimately a subjective judgment -- but this does not change the fact that what we really care about is not the tools named by the shorthand, but the three postulates it attempts to point to.
What does "continuously" in the second postulate mean, BTW. What would happen if we dropped "continuously"?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:12
Let me repeat my question: Might it be the case that we need a marked ruler to create a cone? (Even though you might be saying that this doesn't matter.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:13
@HansStricker: I'm not sure whether "continuously" has any real content here, except perhaps to point out that the original finite straight line together with its extension is supposed to form a single straight line rather than a curve that has a bend where you started extending it. The quotation is from an English translation of the Greek original text, and Euclid was not quite up to today's standard of precision particularly in his basic definitions.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 11:21
To be sure: "straightedge and compass" doesn't allow to draw equidistant marks on the straightedge with the compass (resulting in a marked ruler)? I.e. we may draw a two-dimensional circle in the plane but not a one-dimensional circle on the ruler? We are allowed to do the more complicated but not the more simple? Or do I miss the point?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:48
To sum it up: The straight edge has to be thought of as a beam of light (in which we cannot make marks). We must not think of it as a straight physical body. But how may we think of the compass? Doesn't it have to be a physical body with a definite length? (Nevertheless, Euclidean geometry is about drawing.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 12:07
 |Â
show 8 more comments
up vote
2
down vote
The basic misunderstanding here is that "ruler and compass" is not really about which physical tools you're allowed to use.
When this phrase appears in mathematics it is a shorthand reference to the idea of basing constructions on the three first postulates of Book I of Euclid's Elements:
To draw a straight line from any point to any point.
To produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight line.
To describe a circle with any center and radius.
(The fourth and fifth postulates are not basic constructions but are claims about what happens when certain other combinations of constructions are performed).
These three postulates are the definition of "ruler and compass". Often in English the alternative phrase "compass and straightedge" is preferred, to underscore the fact that there is none of the basic allowed constructions that depend depend on having measuring marks on your ruler.
In fact even without leaving the two-dimensional paper there are things you can imagine doing with a ruler that has measuring marks on it -- so-called neusis constructions. These are nevertheless not part of the basic operations. They can, for example, be used to trisect angles.
Mathematics is not about physical tools. Saying "ruler and compass" is merely supposed to remind you what the fundamental three constructions in Euclid are. You may, if you wish, object that it is a confusing or misleading shorthand -- that is ultimately a subjective judgment -- but this does not change the fact that what we really care about is not the tools named by the shorthand, but the three postulates it attempts to point to.
What does "continuously" in the second postulate mean, BTW. What would happen if we dropped "continuously"?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:12
Let me repeat my question: Might it be the case that we need a marked ruler to create a cone? (Even though you might be saying that this doesn't matter.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:13
@HansStricker: I'm not sure whether "continuously" has any real content here, except perhaps to point out that the original finite straight line together with its extension is supposed to form a single straight line rather than a curve that has a bend where you started extending it. The quotation is from an English translation of the Greek original text, and Euclid was not quite up to today's standard of precision particularly in his basic definitions.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 11:21
To be sure: "straightedge and compass" doesn't allow to draw equidistant marks on the straightedge with the compass (resulting in a marked ruler)? I.e. we may draw a two-dimensional circle in the plane but not a one-dimensional circle on the ruler? We are allowed to do the more complicated but not the more simple? Or do I miss the point?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:48
To sum it up: The straight edge has to be thought of as a beam of light (in which we cannot make marks). We must not think of it as a straight physical body. But how may we think of the compass? Doesn't it have to be a physical body with a definite length? (Nevertheless, Euclidean geometry is about drawing.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 12:07
 |Â
show 8 more comments
up vote
2
down vote
up vote
2
down vote
The basic misunderstanding here is that "ruler and compass" is not really about which physical tools you're allowed to use.
When this phrase appears in mathematics it is a shorthand reference to the idea of basing constructions on the three first postulates of Book I of Euclid's Elements:
To draw a straight line from any point to any point.
To produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight line.
To describe a circle with any center and radius.
(The fourth and fifth postulates are not basic constructions but are claims about what happens when certain other combinations of constructions are performed).
These three postulates are the definition of "ruler and compass". Often in English the alternative phrase "compass and straightedge" is preferred, to underscore the fact that there is none of the basic allowed constructions that depend depend on having measuring marks on your ruler.
In fact even without leaving the two-dimensional paper there are things you can imagine doing with a ruler that has measuring marks on it -- so-called neusis constructions. These are nevertheless not part of the basic operations. They can, for example, be used to trisect angles.
Mathematics is not about physical tools. Saying "ruler and compass" is merely supposed to remind you what the fundamental three constructions in Euclid are. You may, if you wish, object that it is a confusing or misleading shorthand -- that is ultimately a subjective judgment -- but this does not change the fact that what we really care about is not the tools named by the shorthand, but the three postulates it attempts to point to.
The basic misunderstanding here is that "ruler and compass" is not really about which physical tools you're allowed to use.
When this phrase appears in mathematics it is a shorthand reference to the idea of basing constructions on the three first postulates of Book I of Euclid's Elements:
To draw a straight line from any point to any point.
To produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight line.
To describe a circle with any center and radius.
(The fourth and fifth postulates are not basic constructions but are claims about what happens when certain other combinations of constructions are performed).
These three postulates are the definition of "ruler and compass". Often in English the alternative phrase "compass and straightedge" is preferred, to underscore the fact that there is none of the basic allowed constructions that depend depend on having measuring marks on your ruler.
In fact even without leaving the two-dimensional paper there are things you can imagine doing with a ruler that has measuring marks on it -- so-called neusis constructions. These are nevertheless not part of the basic operations. They can, for example, be used to trisect angles.
Mathematics is not about physical tools. Saying "ruler and compass" is merely supposed to remind you what the fundamental three constructions in Euclid are. You may, if you wish, object that it is a confusing or misleading shorthand -- that is ultimately a subjective judgment -- but this does not change the fact that what we really care about is not the tools named by the shorthand, but the three postulates it attempts to point to.
answered Aug 21 at 11:04
Henning Makholm
229k16295526
229k16295526
What does "continuously" in the second postulate mean, BTW. What would happen if we dropped "continuously"?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:12
Let me repeat my question: Might it be the case that we need a marked ruler to create a cone? (Even though you might be saying that this doesn't matter.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:13
@HansStricker: I'm not sure whether "continuously" has any real content here, except perhaps to point out that the original finite straight line together with its extension is supposed to form a single straight line rather than a curve that has a bend where you started extending it. The quotation is from an English translation of the Greek original text, and Euclid was not quite up to today's standard of precision particularly in his basic definitions.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 11:21
To be sure: "straightedge and compass" doesn't allow to draw equidistant marks on the straightedge with the compass (resulting in a marked ruler)? I.e. we may draw a two-dimensional circle in the plane but not a one-dimensional circle on the ruler? We are allowed to do the more complicated but not the more simple? Or do I miss the point?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:48
To sum it up: The straight edge has to be thought of as a beam of light (in which we cannot make marks). We must not think of it as a straight physical body. But how may we think of the compass? Doesn't it have to be a physical body with a definite length? (Nevertheless, Euclidean geometry is about drawing.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 12:07
 |Â
show 8 more comments
What does "continuously" in the second postulate mean, BTW. What would happen if we dropped "continuously"?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:12
Let me repeat my question: Might it be the case that we need a marked ruler to create a cone? (Even though you might be saying that this doesn't matter.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:13
@HansStricker: I'm not sure whether "continuously" has any real content here, except perhaps to point out that the original finite straight line together with its extension is supposed to form a single straight line rather than a curve that has a bend where you started extending it. The quotation is from an English translation of the Greek original text, and Euclid was not quite up to today's standard of precision particularly in his basic definitions.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 11:21
To be sure: "straightedge and compass" doesn't allow to draw equidistant marks on the straightedge with the compass (resulting in a marked ruler)? I.e. we may draw a two-dimensional circle in the plane but not a one-dimensional circle on the ruler? We are allowed to do the more complicated but not the more simple? Or do I miss the point?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:48
To sum it up: The straight edge has to be thought of as a beam of light (in which we cannot make marks). We must not think of it as a straight physical body. But how may we think of the compass? Doesn't it have to be a physical body with a definite length? (Nevertheless, Euclidean geometry is about drawing.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 12:07
What does "continuously" in the second postulate mean, BTW. What would happen if we dropped "continuously"?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:12
What does "continuously" in the second postulate mean, BTW. What would happen if we dropped "continuously"?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:12
Let me repeat my question: Might it be the case that we need a marked ruler to create a cone? (Even though you might be saying that this doesn't matter.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:13
Let me repeat my question: Might it be the case that we need a marked ruler to create a cone? (Even though you might be saying that this doesn't matter.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:13
@HansStricker: I'm not sure whether "continuously" has any real content here, except perhaps to point out that the original finite straight line together with its extension is supposed to form a single straight line rather than a curve that has a bend where you started extending it. The quotation is from an English translation of the Greek original text, and Euclid was not quite up to today's standard of precision particularly in his basic definitions.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 11:21
@HansStricker: I'm not sure whether "continuously" has any real content here, except perhaps to point out that the original finite straight line together with its extension is supposed to form a single straight line rather than a curve that has a bend where you started extending it. The quotation is from an English translation of the Greek original text, and Euclid was not quite up to today's standard of precision particularly in his basic definitions.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 11:21
To be sure: "straightedge and compass" doesn't allow to draw equidistant marks on the straightedge with the compass (resulting in a marked ruler)? I.e. we may draw a two-dimensional circle in the plane but not a one-dimensional circle on the ruler? We are allowed to do the more complicated but not the more simple? Or do I miss the point?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:48
To be sure: "straightedge and compass" doesn't allow to draw equidistant marks on the straightedge with the compass (resulting in a marked ruler)? I.e. we may draw a two-dimensional circle in the plane but not a one-dimensional circle on the ruler? We are allowed to do the more complicated but not the more simple? Or do I miss the point?
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 11:48
To sum it up: The straight edge has to be thought of as a beam of light (in which we cannot make marks). We must not think of it as a straight physical body. But how may we think of the compass? Doesn't it have to be a physical body with a definite length? (Nevertheless, Euclidean geometry is about drawing.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 12:07
To sum it up: The straight edge has to be thought of as a beam of light (in which we cannot make marks). We must not think of it as a straight physical body. But how may we think of the compass? Doesn't it have to be a physical body with a definite length? (Nevertheless, Euclidean geometry is about drawing.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 12:07
 |Â
show 8 more comments
up vote
0
down vote
That's actually very clever! It shows that the ruler and compass model may actually be narrow-minded, since flexible strings are available, as is paper.
However, I believe that if flexible things are not allowed, then we still have unconstructability proofs. For instance, suppose everything we cut out is solid. Then we are only allowed to place it on the plane, and everything we get will have been constructed in the plane before cutting out the shape. So only if we are allowed to bend and stretch things, the third dimension gives additional possibilities.
What could you do without flexibel strings (or let's say flexible rulers)? How would you measure the length of the circumference of a circle? (This is what you must do: 1. Draw a circle on a piece of wood. 2. Cut it out perfectly. 3. Lay the flexibel ruler around it. 4. Create a straight ruler of equal length.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:57
add a comment |Â
up vote
0
down vote
That's actually very clever! It shows that the ruler and compass model may actually be narrow-minded, since flexible strings are available, as is paper.
However, I believe that if flexible things are not allowed, then we still have unconstructability proofs. For instance, suppose everything we cut out is solid. Then we are only allowed to place it on the plane, and everything we get will have been constructed in the plane before cutting out the shape. So only if we are allowed to bend and stretch things, the third dimension gives additional possibilities.
What could you do without flexibel strings (or let's say flexible rulers)? How would you measure the length of the circumference of a circle? (This is what you must do: 1. Draw a circle on a piece of wood. 2. Cut it out perfectly. 3. Lay the flexibel ruler around it. 4. Create a straight ruler of equal length.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:57
add a comment |Â
up vote
0
down vote
up vote
0
down vote
That's actually very clever! It shows that the ruler and compass model may actually be narrow-minded, since flexible strings are available, as is paper.
However, I believe that if flexible things are not allowed, then we still have unconstructability proofs. For instance, suppose everything we cut out is solid. Then we are only allowed to place it on the plane, and everything we get will have been constructed in the plane before cutting out the shape. So only if we are allowed to bend and stretch things, the third dimension gives additional possibilities.
That's actually very clever! It shows that the ruler and compass model may actually be narrow-minded, since flexible strings are available, as is paper.
However, I believe that if flexible things are not allowed, then we still have unconstructability proofs. For instance, suppose everything we cut out is solid. Then we are only allowed to place it on the plane, and everything we get will have been constructed in the plane before cutting out the shape. So only if we are allowed to bend and stretch things, the third dimension gives additional possibilities.
answered Aug 21 at 10:37
AlgebraicsAnonymous
94611
94611
What could you do without flexibel strings (or let's say flexible rulers)? How would you measure the length of the circumference of a circle? (This is what you must do: 1. Draw a circle on a piece of wood. 2. Cut it out perfectly. 3. Lay the flexibel ruler around it. 4. Create a straight ruler of equal length.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:57
add a comment |Â
What could you do without flexibel strings (or let's say flexible rulers)? How would you measure the length of the circumference of a circle? (This is what you must do: 1. Draw a circle on a piece of wood. 2. Cut it out perfectly. 3. Lay the flexibel ruler around it. 4. Create a straight ruler of equal length.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:57
What could you do without flexibel strings (or let's say flexible rulers)? How would you measure the length of the circumference of a circle? (This is what you must do: 1. Draw a circle on a piece of wood. 2. Cut it out perfectly. 3. Lay the flexibel ruler around it. 4. Create a straight ruler of equal length.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:57
What could you do without flexibel strings (or let's say flexible rulers)? How would you measure the length of the circumference of a circle? (This is what you must do: 1. Draw a circle on a piece of wood. 2. Cut it out perfectly. 3. Lay the flexibel ruler around it. 4. Create a straight ruler of equal length.)
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:57
add a comment |Â
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2889690%2fconstruction-of-arbitrary-regular-polygons-with-ruler-and-compass%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
How do you project vertically with compass and ruler? Is plane construction through a point perpendicular to another plane a known thing?
â dEmigOd
Aug 21 at 10:27
That's the kind of objections I was asking for. One could use the light of the sun (at least the ancient Greeks could have come upon this).
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:32
If you are talking about light of the sun, then should not beams be actually not parallel, nor gravitational pull, as it supposed to be directed to the center of the earth.
â dEmigOd
Aug 21 at 10:42
1
You can also do things with a marked ruler that compass and straightedge are not able to. -- Even though you can certainly draw a picture of the marked ruler with a straightedge, that does not count as a "compass and straightedge" construction.
â Henning Makholm
Aug 21 at 10:46
@dEmigOd: The greeks - when they were to think about it - would most surely have assumed, that the light of the sun comes in parallel.
â Hans Stricker
Aug 21 at 10:54