When I say that $[0,1]/_sim$ is the circle, do I have to prove it or it's obvious?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
4
down vote

favorite












I saw on wikipedia that quotient topology doesn't behaves well in the sense that $X$ can be metrizable, haussdorf... but $X/_!sim$ not. We can see that gluing $0$ and $1$ in the segment $[0,1]$ gives the circle. But do I really have to prove it or such construction is clear by visualizing ? Same if I take $[0,1]times [0,1]$ and I glue all point of the boundary in one, we "see" that it's going to be the sphere $mathbb S^2$. Do I have to prove it rigorously, or it's not really necessary ?



I'm asking this because in a course notes on manifold I'm reading, the teacher say always : "we see that gluing $A$ and $B$ gives torus, or sphere or any geometric figure", but he doesn't prove it rigorously. I sent him an email yesterday, and he sais that such argument is enough to identify things. Is it really the case ? I mean, if the quotient doesn't behaves well, we have to prove rigorously that such identification gives the sphere or the torus (or anything else), no ?



Can someone gives me an example where we expect that a quotient $X/_sim$ we'll be a specific figure, but in fact it will not be ?










share|cite|improve this question

























    up vote
    4
    down vote

    favorite












    I saw on wikipedia that quotient topology doesn't behaves well in the sense that $X$ can be metrizable, haussdorf... but $X/_!sim$ not. We can see that gluing $0$ and $1$ in the segment $[0,1]$ gives the circle. But do I really have to prove it or such construction is clear by visualizing ? Same if I take $[0,1]times [0,1]$ and I glue all point of the boundary in one, we "see" that it's going to be the sphere $mathbb S^2$. Do I have to prove it rigorously, or it's not really necessary ?



    I'm asking this because in a course notes on manifold I'm reading, the teacher say always : "we see that gluing $A$ and $B$ gives torus, or sphere or any geometric figure", but he doesn't prove it rigorously. I sent him an email yesterday, and he sais that such argument is enough to identify things. Is it really the case ? I mean, if the quotient doesn't behaves well, we have to prove rigorously that such identification gives the sphere or the torus (or anything else), no ?



    Can someone gives me an example where we expect that a quotient $X/_sim$ we'll be a specific figure, but in fact it will not be ?










    share|cite|improve this question























      up vote
      4
      down vote

      favorite









      up vote
      4
      down vote

      favorite











      I saw on wikipedia that quotient topology doesn't behaves well in the sense that $X$ can be metrizable, haussdorf... but $X/_!sim$ not. We can see that gluing $0$ and $1$ in the segment $[0,1]$ gives the circle. But do I really have to prove it or such construction is clear by visualizing ? Same if I take $[0,1]times [0,1]$ and I glue all point of the boundary in one, we "see" that it's going to be the sphere $mathbb S^2$. Do I have to prove it rigorously, or it's not really necessary ?



      I'm asking this because in a course notes on manifold I'm reading, the teacher say always : "we see that gluing $A$ and $B$ gives torus, or sphere or any geometric figure", but he doesn't prove it rigorously. I sent him an email yesterday, and he sais that such argument is enough to identify things. Is it really the case ? I mean, if the quotient doesn't behaves well, we have to prove rigorously that such identification gives the sphere or the torus (or anything else), no ?



      Can someone gives me an example where we expect that a quotient $X/_sim$ we'll be a specific figure, but in fact it will not be ?










      share|cite|improve this question













      I saw on wikipedia that quotient topology doesn't behaves well in the sense that $X$ can be metrizable, haussdorf... but $X/_!sim$ not. We can see that gluing $0$ and $1$ in the segment $[0,1]$ gives the circle. But do I really have to prove it or such construction is clear by visualizing ? Same if I take $[0,1]times [0,1]$ and I glue all point of the boundary in one, we "see" that it's going to be the sphere $mathbb S^2$. Do I have to prove it rigorously, or it's not really necessary ?



      I'm asking this because in a course notes on manifold I'm reading, the teacher say always : "we see that gluing $A$ and $B$ gives torus, or sphere or any geometric figure", but he doesn't prove it rigorously. I sent him an email yesterday, and he sais that such argument is enough to identify things. Is it really the case ? I mean, if the quotient doesn't behaves well, we have to prove rigorously that such identification gives the sphere or the torus (or anything else), no ?



      Can someone gives me an example where we expect that a quotient $X/_sim$ we'll be a specific figure, but in fact it will not be ?







      general-topology manifolds






      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question











      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question










      asked Sep 5 at 10:16









      user386627

      809215




      809215




















          2 Answers
          2






          active

          oldest

          votes

















          up vote
          5
          down vote













          I think, perhaps, you are missing the point of why you would or would not prove that the gluing construction gives the desired shape. We intuitively have an idea of what the gluing operation looks like: if I give you an interval, and tell you to glue the two end points, then you know that the outcome should be the circle. If I give you a square and tell you to identify two opposite sides in opposite directions, you know the outcome should be the Möbius strip.



          However, the "gluing operation" is an abstract mathematical operation, applied on an object (a topology) which is often counterintuitive.



          Thus, if the construction of the circle or the Möbius strip fails, it is not because we have badly predicted what the outcome shape should be, but because the gluing operation is wrong. The point of proving a few examples early on of the effect of the gluing operation -- at one point I proved in an introductory topology class that identifying the end points of an interval really gives a circle -- is to convince oneself that the gluing operation is really what it promises to be. After doing a few of these, you notice that the construction goes the same way every time, and you trust that it will go the same way with every other pictorial example.






          share|cite|improve this answer



























            up vote
            1
            down vote













            Being "obvious" is always a subjective evaluation, similarly as being "trivial". It depends on your knowledge and your experience. For a beginner less things will be obvious than for a person having been active in mathematics for many years.



            Saying that something is obvious can have various reasons, for example



            (1) It is a known result which has explicitly been proved, but the proof is very simple so that virtually everybody can work it out.



            (2) It is very similar to something you know to be true, and you know that the proven methods apply. This is professional experience.



            Of course there is also a danger in taking something for obvious: The devil may be in the details, and professional experience may fail. I am sure that the literature contains numerous examples of erroneous proofs (or even erroneous results) rooting in a feeling of obviousness.



            Let us come back from philosophy to your examples concerning "glueing". This is definitively category (1). Other examples are statements like "a circle is homeomorphic to a square", "a teacup is homeomorphic to solid torus", etc.



            As Mees de Vries said in his answer, if you explicitly work out some of such examples, you will develop an understanding for what is going on and end with the judgement "Yes, it is obvious".






            share|cite|improve this answer




















              Your Answer




              StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
              return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
              StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
              StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
              );
              );
              , "mathjax-editing");

              StackExchange.ready(function()
              var channelOptions =
              tags: "".split(" "),
              id: "69"
              ;
              initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

              StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
              // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
              if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
              StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
              createEditor();
              );

              else
              createEditor();

              );

              function createEditor()
              StackExchange.prepareEditor(
              heartbeatType: 'answer',
              convertImagesToLinks: true,
              noModals: false,
              showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
              reputationToPostImages: 10,
              bindNavPrevention: true,
              postfix: "",
              noCode: true, onDemand: true,
              discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
              ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
              );



              );













               

              draft saved


              draft discarded


















              StackExchange.ready(
              function ()
              StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2906100%2fwhen-i-say-that-0-1-sim-is-the-circle-do-i-have-to-prove-it-or-its-obvio%23new-answer', 'question_page');

              );

              Post as a guest






























              2 Answers
              2






              active

              oldest

              votes








              2 Answers
              2






              active

              oldest

              votes









              active

              oldest

              votes






              active

              oldest

              votes








              up vote
              5
              down vote













              I think, perhaps, you are missing the point of why you would or would not prove that the gluing construction gives the desired shape. We intuitively have an idea of what the gluing operation looks like: if I give you an interval, and tell you to glue the two end points, then you know that the outcome should be the circle. If I give you a square and tell you to identify two opposite sides in opposite directions, you know the outcome should be the Möbius strip.



              However, the "gluing operation" is an abstract mathematical operation, applied on an object (a topology) which is often counterintuitive.



              Thus, if the construction of the circle or the Möbius strip fails, it is not because we have badly predicted what the outcome shape should be, but because the gluing operation is wrong. The point of proving a few examples early on of the effect of the gluing operation -- at one point I proved in an introductory topology class that identifying the end points of an interval really gives a circle -- is to convince oneself that the gluing operation is really what it promises to be. After doing a few of these, you notice that the construction goes the same way every time, and you trust that it will go the same way with every other pictorial example.






              share|cite|improve this answer
























                up vote
                5
                down vote













                I think, perhaps, you are missing the point of why you would or would not prove that the gluing construction gives the desired shape. We intuitively have an idea of what the gluing operation looks like: if I give you an interval, and tell you to glue the two end points, then you know that the outcome should be the circle. If I give you a square and tell you to identify two opposite sides in opposite directions, you know the outcome should be the Möbius strip.



                However, the "gluing operation" is an abstract mathematical operation, applied on an object (a topology) which is often counterintuitive.



                Thus, if the construction of the circle or the Möbius strip fails, it is not because we have badly predicted what the outcome shape should be, but because the gluing operation is wrong. The point of proving a few examples early on of the effect of the gluing operation -- at one point I proved in an introductory topology class that identifying the end points of an interval really gives a circle -- is to convince oneself that the gluing operation is really what it promises to be. After doing a few of these, you notice that the construction goes the same way every time, and you trust that it will go the same way with every other pictorial example.






                share|cite|improve this answer






















                  up vote
                  5
                  down vote










                  up vote
                  5
                  down vote









                  I think, perhaps, you are missing the point of why you would or would not prove that the gluing construction gives the desired shape. We intuitively have an idea of what the gluing operation looks like: if I give you an interval, and tell you to glue the two end points, then you know that the outcome should be the circle. If I give you a square and tell you to identify two opposite sides in opposite directions, you know the outcome should be the Möbius strip.



                  However, the "gluing operation" is an abstract mathematical operation, applied on an object (a topology) which is often counterintuitive.



                  Thus, if the construction of the circle or the Möbius strip fails, it is not because we have badly predicted what the outcome shape should be, but because the gluing operation is wrong. The point of proving a few examples early on of the effect of the gluing operation -- at one point I proved in an introductory topology class that identifying the end points of an interval really gives a circle -- is to convince oneself that the gluing operation is really what it promises to be. After doing a few of these, you notice that the construction goes the same way every time, and you trust that it will go the same way with every other pictorial example.






                  share|cite|improve this answer












                  I think, perhaps, you are missing the point of why you would or would not prove that the gluing construction gives the desired shape. We intuitively have an idea of what the gluing operation looks like: if I give you an interval, and tell you to glue the two end points, then you know that the outcome should be the circle. If I give you a square and tell you to identify two opposite sides in opposite directions, you know the outcome should be the Möbius strip.



                  However, the "gluing operation" is an abstract mathematical operation, applied on an object (a topology) which is often counterintuitive.



                  Thus, if the construction of the circle or the Möbius strip fails, it is not because we have badly predicted what the outcome shape should be, but because the gluing operation is wrong. The point of proving a few examples early on of the effect of the gluing operation -- at one point I proved in an introductory topology class that identifying the end points of an interval really gives a circle -- is to convince oneself that the gluing operation is really what it promises to be. After doing a few of these, you notice that the construction goes the same way every time, and you trust that it will go the same way with every other pictorial example.







                  share|cite|improve this answer












                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer










                  answered Sep 5 at 10:39









                  Mees de Vries

                  14.4k12348




                  14.4k12348




















                      up vote
                      1
                      down vote













                      Being "obvious" is always a subjective evaluation, similarly as being "trivial". It depends on your knowledge and your experience. For a beginner less things will be obvious than for a person having been active in mathematics for many years.



                      Saying that something is obvious can have various reasons, for example



                      (1) It is a known result which has explicitly been proved, but the proof is very simple so that virtually everybody can work it out.



                      (2) It is very similar to something you know to be true, and you know that the proven methods apply. This is professional experience.



                      Of course there is also a danger in taking something for obvious: The devil may be in the details, and professional experience may fail. I am sure that the literature contains numerous examples of erroneous proofs (or even erroneous results) rooting in a feeling of obviousness.



                      Let us come back from philosophy to your examples concerning "glueing". This is definitively category (1). Other examples are statements like "a circle is homeomorphic to a square", "a teacup is homeomorphic to solid torus", etc.



                      As Mees de Vries said in his answer, if you explicitly work out some of such examples, you will develop an understanding for what is going on and end with the judgement "Yes, it is obvious".






                      share|cite|improve this answer
























                        up vote
                        1
                        down vote













                        Being "obvious" is always a subjective evaluation, similarly as being "trivial". It depends on your knowledge and your experience. For a beginner less things will be obvious than for a person having been active in mathematics for many years.



                        Saying that something is obvious can have various reasons, for example



                        (1) It is a known result which has explicitly been proved, but the proof is very simple so that virtually everybody can work it out.



                        (2) It is very similar to something you know to be true, and you know that the proven methods apply. This is professional experience.



                        Of course there is also a danger in taking something for obvious: The devil may be in the details, and professional experience may fail. I am sure that the literature contains numerous examples of erroneous proofs (or even erroneous results) rooting in a feeling of obviousness.



                        Let us come back from philosophy to your examples concerning "glueing". This is definitively category (1). Other examples are statements like "a circle is homeomorphic to a square", "a teacup is homeomorphic to solid torus", etc.



                        As Mees de Vries said in his answer, if you explicitly work out some of such examples, you will develop an understanding for what is going on and end with the judgement "Yes, it is obvious".






                        share|cite|improve this answer






















                          up vote
                          1
                          down vote










                          up vote
                          1
                          down vote









                          Being "obvious" is always a subjective evaluation, similarly as being "trivial". It depends on your knowledge and your experience. For a beginner less things will be obvious than for a person having been active in mathematics for many years.



                          Saying that something is obvious can have various reasons, for example



                          (1) It is a known result which has explicitly been proved, but the proof is very simple so that virtually everybody can work it out.



                          (2) It is very similar to something you know to be true, and you know that the proven methods apply. This is professional experience.



                          Of course there is also a danger in taking something for obvious: The devil may be in the details, and professional experience may fail. I am sure that the literature contains numerous examples of erroneous proofs (or even erroneous results) rooting in a feeling of obviousness.



                          Let us come back from philosophy to your examples concerning "glueing". This is definitively category (1). Other examples are statements like "a circle is homeomorphic to a square", "a teacup is homeomorphic to solid torus", etc.



                          As Mees de Vries said in his answer, if you explicitly work out some of such examples, you will develop an understanding for what is going on and end with the judgement "Yes, it is obvious".






                          share|cite|improve this answer












                          Being "obvious" is always a subjective evaluation, similarly as being "trivial". It depends on your knowledge and your experience. For a beginner less things will be obvious than for a person having been active in mathematics for many years.



                          Saying that something is obvious can have various reasons, for example



                          (1) It is a known result which has explicitly been proved, but the proof is very simple so that virtually everybody can work it out.



                          (2) It is very similar to something you know to be true, and you know that the proven methods apply. This is professional experience.



                          Of course there is also a danger in taking something for obvious: The devil may be in the details, and professional experience may fail. I am sure that the literature contains numerous examples of erroneous proofs (or even erroneous results) rooting in a feeling of obviousness.



                          Let us come back from philosophy to your examples concerning "glueing". This is definitively category (1). Other examples are statements like "a circle is homeomorphic to a square", "a teacup is homeomorphic to solid torus", etc.



                          As Mees de Vries said in his answer, if you explicitly work out some of such examples, you will develop an understanding for what is going on and end with the judgement "Yes, it is obvious".







                          share|cite|improve this answer












                          share|cite|improve this answer



                          share|cite|improve this answer










                          answered Sep 5 at 16:27









                          Paul Frost

                          4,853424




                          4,853424



























                               

                              draft saved


                              draft discarded















































                               


                              draft saved


                              draft discarded














                              StackExchange.ready(
                              function ()
                              StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2906100%2fwhen-i-say-that-0-1-sim-is-the-circle-do-i-have-to-prove-it-or-its-obvio%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                              );

                              Post as a guest













































































                              這個網誌中的熱門文章

                              How to combine Bézier curves to a surface?

                              Carbon dioxide

                              Why am i infinitely getting the same tweet with the Twitter Search API?