How to prove that the converse of Lagrange's theorem is not true?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
3
down vote

favorite
1












I consider the Lagrange theorem.
Let $G$ be a finite group and let $H subseteq G$ be a subgroup, then the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$.
I am interesting with the proof of this theorem. The proof is as follows



Let $C= a_1 H, a_2 H,ldots,a_t H$ be a collection of all distinct left cosets of $H$ in $G$, where $t$ is a positive integer.
Since $C$ is a partition of $G$ ,we have
$|G|=|a_1 H|+|a_2 H|+ldots+|a_t H|=|H|+|H|+….+|H|=t|H|$, hence the theorem is proved!



Now how can I prove that the converse of this theorem is not true? Is the converse not true generally ?



Here is the way I try, from $|G|=|a_1 H|+|a_2 H|+ldots+|a_t H| = |H|+|H|+ldots+|H|=t |H|$. If I try to write $|H|/|G|=1/t$, I see that $1/t$ is not an integer, so that the converse of Lagrange theorem is not true. Does this satisfy for the proof “converse of Lagrange's theorem is not true”? Please I beg your more help for this case, thanks







share|cite|improve this question






















  • Could you state what you think the converse is? I think it should be: "If $n$ divides $|G|$, then there is a subgroup $H$ of $G$ with $|H| = n$." This does not hold in general.
    – Dylan Moreland
    Jan 21 '12 at 4:52















up vote
3
down vote

favorite
1












I consider the Lagrange theorem.
Let $G$ be a finite group and let $H subseteq G$ be a subgroup, then the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$.
I am interesting with the proof of this theorem. The proof is as follows



Let $C= a_1 H, a_2 H,ldots,a_t H$ be a collection of all distinct left cosets of $H$ in $G$, where $t$ is a positive integer.
Since $C$ is a partition of $G$ ,we have
$|G|=|a_1 H|+|a_2 H|+ldots+|a_t H|=|H|+|H|+….+|H|=t|H|$, hence the theorem is proved!



Now how can I prove that the converse of this theorem is not true? Is the converse not true generally ?



Here is the way I try, from $|G|=|a_1 H|+|a_2 H|+ldots+|a_t H| = |H|+|H|+ldots+|H|=t |H|$. If I try to write $|H|/|G|=1/t$, I see that $1/t$ is not an integer, so that the converse of Lagrange theorem is not true. Does this satisfy for the proof “converse of Lagrange's theorem is not true”? Please I beg your more help for this case, thanks







share|cite|improve this question






















  • Could you state what you think the converse is? I think it should be: "If $n$ divides $|G|$, then there is a subgroup $H$ of $G$ with $|H| = n$." This does not hold in general.
    – Dylan Moreland
    Jan 21 '12 at 4:52













up vote
3
down vote

favorite
1









up vote
3
down vote

favorite
1






1





I consider the Lagrange theorem.
Let $G$ be a finite group and let $H subseteq G$ be a subgroup, then the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$.
I am interesting with the proof of this theorem. The proof is as follows



Let $C= a_1 H, a_2 H,ldots,a_t H$ be a collection of all distinct left cosets of $H$ in $G$, where $t$ is a positive integer.
Since $C$ is a partition of $G$ ,we have
$|G|=|a_1 H|+|a_2 H|+ldots+|a_t H|=|H|+|H|+….+|H|=t|H|$, hence the theorem is proved!



Now how can I prove that the converse of this theorem is not true? Is the converse not true generally ?



Here is the way I try, from $|G|=|a_1 H|+|a_2 H|+ldots+|a_t H| = |H|+|H|+ldots+|H|=t |H|$. If I try to write $|H|/|G|=1/t$, I see that $1/t$ is not an integer, so that the converse of Lagrange theorem is not true. Does this satisfy for the proof “converse of Lagrange's theorem is not true”? Please I beg your more help for this case, thanks







share|cite|improve this question














I consider the Lagrange theorem.
Let $G$ be a finite group and let $H subseteq G$ be a subgroup, then the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$.
I am interesting with the proof of this theorem. The proof is as follows



Let $C= a_1 H, a_2 H,ldots,a_t H$ be a collection of all distinct left cosets of $H$ in $G$, where $t$ is a positive integer.
Since $C$ is a partition of $G$ ,we have
$|G|=|a_1 H|+|a_2 H|+ldots+|a_t H|=|H|+|H|+….+|H|=t|H|$, hence the theorem is proved!



Now how can I prove that the converse of this theorem is not true? Is the converse not true generally ?



Here is the way I try, from $|G|=|a_1 H|+|a_2 H|+ldots+|a_t H| = |H|+|H|+ldots+|H|=t |H|$. If I try to write $|H|/|G|=1/t$, I see that $1/t$ is not an integer, so that the converse of Lagrange theorem is not true. Does this satisfy for the proof “converse of Lagrange's theorem is not true”? Please I beg your more help for this case, thanks









share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jan 21 '12 at 10:35









Martin Sleziak

43.6k6113260




43.6k6113260










asked Jan 21 '12 at 4:45









wami.

1813




1813











  • Could you state what you think the converse is? I think it should be: "If $n$ divides $|G|$, then there is a subgroup $H$ of $G$ with $|H| = n$." This does not hold in general.
    – Dylan Moreland
    Jan 21 '12 at 4:52

















  • Could you state what you think the converse is? I think it should be: "If $n$ divides $|G|$, then there is a subgroup $H$ of $G$ with $|H| = n$." This does not hold in general.
    – Dylan Moreland
    Jan 21 '12 at 4:52
















Could you state what you think the converse is? I think it should be: "If $n$ divides $|G|$, then there is a subgroup $H$ of $G$ with $|H| = n$." This does not hold in general.
– Dylan Moreland
Jan 21 '12 at 4:52





Could you state what you think the converse is? I think it should be: "If $n$ divides $|G|$, then there is a subgroup $H$ of $G$ with $|H| = n$." This does not hold in general.
– Dylan Moreland
Jan 21 '12 at 4:52











4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
12
down vote



accepted










When you have an implication, "if $P$, then $Q$", the converse is the implication "if $Q$, then $P$."



Lagrange's Theorem says:




Let $G$ be finite with $|G|=n$. If $d$ is the order of a subgroup of $G$, then $d$ divides $n$.




The converse would therefore say:




Let $G$ be a finite group with $|G|=n$. If $d$ divides $n$, then $d$ is the order of a subgroup of $G$.




This is an implication. In order to show that an implication is false, you need to show that it is possible for the antecedent ("$d$ divides $n$") to be true and at the same time, the consequence ("$d$ is the order of a subgroup of $H$") to be false.



So in order to show that the converse of Lagrange's Theorem is not true, what you need to do is:



  1. Exhibit a specific finite group $G$;

  2. Exhibit a specific number $d$ that divides $G$; and

  3. Prove that $G$ does not have any subgroups of order $d$.

In other words, you need to give an example that shows that the converse statement does not have to be true. (A "counterexample".)



What you did makes no sense, and does not prove anything. The "converse" has nothing to do with the reciprocal $|H|/|G|$, and is certainly not an assertion that the order of $G$ divides the order of $H$.



Now, just to help in your search: if $G$ is abelian, then it will satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem, so try looking for nonabelian groups; if $|G|$ is a power of a prime, or the product of two distinct primes, then $G$ will satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem as well, so avoid those. But try the very smallest size that is left once you throw out all of those orders.






share|cite|improve this answer






















  • :Thanks for help, am now okay
    – wami.
    Jan 21 '12 at 5:18










  • what about if I consider the Alternating group A4?.
    – wami.
    Jan 21 '12 at 9:01










  • @wami: That's a good place to look, certainly.
    – Arturo Magidin
    Jan 21 '12 at 21:53










  • @ArturoMagidin , may you show plz , why does if the order of the group is a pwoer of a prime then , the converse of lagrange hold ?.the converse hold in the case when , $|G|=pq$, $qleqslant p$ where $q$ doesn't divide $(p-1)$ as $G$ is abelian here , is this what you mean about the holding of the converse when the order is the product of two primes ? what if $q$ divides $p-q$ , does the converse hold ?
    – Fawzy Hegab
    Jun 18 '13 at 5:14


















up vote
3
down vote













In the positive direction, it is easiest to note that if $G$ is a finite cyclic group of order $n$ and $k$ divides $n$, then $G$ has a subgroup of order $k$. It is generated by $a^n/k$ if $a$ generates $G$. This can be extended to (finite) abelian groups because they are direct sums of cyclic groups.



Every supersolvable group also satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem, and every group that satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem is solvable. This was shown by Bray in "A note on CLT groups," 1968. Every subgroup and every quotient of a supersolvable group is supersolvable, hence satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem.



As Arturo noted, standard results of group theory show that there can be no counterexample whose order is a power of a prime or a product of two distinct primes. But there are other numbers, like $20=2^2cdot 5$, for which every group with that number of elements satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem. There have been several articles written both on the possible orders of groups that don't satisfy the converse as well as other properties of such groups. One example is a result of Struik in "Partial converses to Lagrange's theorem,", 1978. To quote part of the review by Humphreys (because I don't have the article):




Let $p$ and $q$ be distinct primes with $p$ not dividing $q-1$ and $q$ not dividing $p-1$. Let $e$ be the exponent of $p textmod,q$ and $f$ be the exponent of $q textmod,p$. Then $p^aq^b$ is a CLT number if and only if one of the following four conditions is satisfied: (i) $a<e$ and $b<f$; (ii) $e$ is odd, $a=2e-1$ and $b<f$; (iii) $f$ is odd, $b=2f-1$ and $a<e$; (iv) $e$ and $f$ are both odd, $a=2e-1$ and $b=2f-1$.




For example, if $p=3$ and $q=5$, then $e=4$ and $f=2$, so by part (i) we see that every group of order $45=3^2cdot 5$ or $135=3^3cdot 5$ satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem. It is known (as seen for example in Curran's "Non-CLT groups of small order" where such groups are studied) that the numbers less than $100$ that are orders of groups that don't satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem are the following: $12,24,36,48,56,60,72,75,80,84$ and $96$.



(I didn't know any of the results from these articles, but I searched because the question made me interested.)






share|cite|improve this answer


















  • 1




    See also this question and this one.
    – Arturo Magidin
    Jan 21 '12 at 22:42










  • @Arturo: Thanks very much, I hadn't seen those.
    – Jonas Meyer
    Jan 21 '12 at 22:57

















up vote
0
down vote













What the converse of a theorem is depends on exactly how it is formulated, and in the formulation you gave there is no converse. As Arturo said you need a statement of the form "if $P$ then $Q$" to turn into the converse "if $Q$ then $P$" (or if you prefer "if not $P$ then not $Q$, which is logically equivalent). However your statement does not contain the word "if", so strictly speaking there is no converse.



Arturo gave an equivalent statement that does contain the word "if", and proved that the converse to that statement is false. However his formulation is rather distant from yours, notably he introduces $d$ that is not mentioned in your statement at all (and the mention of $H$ is dropped). A closer approximation would be the formulation "Let $G$ be a finite group. If $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, then the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$". The converse of this statement is "Let $G$ be a finite group. If the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$, then $H$ is a subgroup of $G$". The problem with this statement is that $H$ now comes out of the blue; since we have to prove that $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, we may not assume that in interpreting the "if" part, and we have the problem that, without any assumption on $H$, the phrase "the order of $H$" makes no sense. So with this approach there is still no sensible converse to prove. A solution would be to expand "the order of $H$" to "the number of elements of $H$", which makes sense whenever $H$ is a set. If we add a clause stipulating that before the "if", we get as original statement "Let $G$ be a finite group and $H$ a set. If $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, then the number of elements of $H$ divides the order of $G$", which has a sensible (but clearly false) converse "Let $G$ be a finite group and $H$ a set. If the number of elements of $H$ divides the order of $G$, then $H$ is a subgroup of $G$." I'm sure you are able to find counterexamples to the latter statement easily.



The morale of the story is that "the converse" of an arbitrary statement is not well defined, and if it is, it could be nonsensical; even if the converse makes, the converse of a different but equivalent formulation of the same fact could be inequivalent to the original converse, and one can imagine one of them being true and another false. In the current case we have not found any "converse" that is actually true, but as an exercise you may try to find one... (A somewhat cheating trivial solution to this exercise is that, being a proven statement, Lagrange's Theorem is formally equivalent to every other proven statement, in the sense that assuming one of them you can prove the other. Now choose any proven statement whose converse happens to be proven as well.)






share|cite|improve this answer



























    up vote
    -1
    down vote













    Lagranges theorem



    $$H<G---->|G|/|H|$$



    the converse says



    $$|G|/|H|----->H<G$$



    And the converse is not true, because A4 is a counter example and A4 is a group of oder 12 having no subgroup of order 6.



    Proof:



    A4 contains eight 3 cycles of the form (abc) and three pairs of disjoint transposition of the form (ab)(cd) and an identity element where a, b, c, d are disjoint elements.



    If a sub group contains 3 cycles (abc) it must also contain it's inverse (acb).



    If a sub group of order 6 exists then it must contain an identity element, a pair of transposition because the odd number of non identity elements cannot just be 3cycles (abc) and their inverses.



    If A4 contains a sub group of order 6 it must contain at least two pairs of transposition because A4 contains only four elements that are not 3cycles.



    And so without loss of generality:



    Suppose the sub group of order 6 contains (abc) it must also contain(acb) it's inverse and since it contains a pair of transposition (ab)(cd) such that when we multiply the group is closed so (abc) (ab)(cd)=(bdc).



    The inverse of (bdc)=(bcd)



    (ab)(cd)(abc)=(acd)



    (acd)invesre =(adc)



    And then the identity elements which all together makes up more than 6 elements and so A4 has no subgroup of order 6.






    share|cite|improve this answer






















    • Your answer did not get formatted right. COuld you please edit it?
      – Cornman
      Aug 27 at 1:08










    Your Answer




    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    );
    );
    , "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function()
    var channelOptions =
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    ;
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
    createEditor();
    );

    else
    createEditor();

    );

    function createEditor()
    StackExchange.prepareEditor(
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: false,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    );



    );













     

    draft saved


    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function ()
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f100933%2fhow-to-prove-that-the-converse-of-lagranges-theorem-is-not-true%23new-answer', 'question_page');

    );

    Post as a guest






























    4 Answers
    4






    active

    oldest

    votes








    4 Answers
    4






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes








    up vote
    12
    down vote



    accepted










    When you have an implication, "if $P$, then $Q$", the converse is the implication "if $Q$, then $P$."



    Lagrange's Theorem says:




    Let $G$ be finite with $|G|=n$. If $d$ is the order of a subgroup of $G$, then $d$ divides $n$.




    The converse would therefore say:




    Let $G$ be a finite group with $|G|=n$. If $d$ divides $n$, then $d$ is the order of a subgroup of $G$.




    This is an implication. In order to show that an implication is false, you need to show that it is possible for the antecedent ("$d$ divides $n$") to be true and at the same time, the consequence ("$d$ is the order of a subgroup of $H$") to be false.



    So in order to show that the converse of Lagrange's Theorem is not true, what you need to do is:



    1. Exhibit a specific finite group $G$;

    2. Exhibit a specific number $d$ that divides $G$; and

    3. Prove that $G$ does not have any subgroups of order $d$.

    In other words, you need to give an example that shows that the converse statement does not have to be true. (A "counterexample".)



    What you did makes no sense, and does not prove anything. The "converse" has nothing to do with the reciprocal $|H|/|G|$, and is certainly not an assertion that the order of $G$ divides the order of $H$.



    Now, just to help in your search: if $G$ is abelian, then it will satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem, so try looking for nonabelian groups; if $|G|$ is a power of a prime, or the product of two distinct primes, then $G$ will satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem as well, so avoid those. But try the very smallest size that is left once you throw out all of those orders.






    share|cite|improve this answer






















    • :Thanks for help, am now okay
      – wami.
      Jan 21 '12 at 5:18










    • what about if I consider the Alternating group A4?.
      – wami.
      Jan 21 '12 at 9:01










    • @wami: That's a good place to look, certainly.
      – Arturo Magidin
      Jan 21 '12 at 21:53










    • @ArturoMagidin , may you show plz , why does if the order of the group is a pwoer of a prime then , the converse of lagrange hold ?.the converse hold in the case when , $|G|=pq$, $qleqslant p$ where $q$ doesn't divide $(p-1)$ as $G$ is abelian here , is this what you mean about the holding of the converse when the order is the product of two primes ? what if $q$ divides $p-q$ , does the converse hold ?
      – Fawzy Hegab
      Jun 18 '13 at 5:14















    up vote
    12
    down vote



    accepted










    When you have an implication, "if $P$, then $Q$", the converse is the implication "if $Q$, then $P$."



    Lagrange's Theorem says:




    Let $G$ be finite with $|G|=n$. If $d$ is the order of a subgroup of $G$, then $d$ divides $n$.




    The converse would therefore say:




    Let $G$ be a finite group with $|G|=n$. If $d$ divides $n$, then $d$ is the order of a subgroup of $G$.




    This is an implication. In order to show that an implication is false, you need to show that it is possible for the antecedent ("$d$ divides $n$") to be true and at the same time, the consequence ("$d$ is the order of a subgroup of $H$") to be false.



    So in order to show that the converse of Lagrange's Theorem is not true, what you need to do is:



    1. Exhibit a specific finite group $G$;

    2. Exhibit a specific number $d$ that divides $G$; and

    3. Prove that $G$ does not have any subgroups of order $d$.

    In other words, you need to give an example that shows that the converse statement does not have to be true. (A "counterexample".)



    What you did makes no sense, and does not prove anything. The "converse" has nothing to do with the reciprocal $|H|/|G|$, and is certainly not an assertion that the order of $G$ divides the order of $H$.



    Now, just to help in your search: if $G$ is abelian, then it will satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem, so try looking for nonabelian groups; if $|G|$ is a power of a prime, or the product of two distinct primes, then $G$ will satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem as well, so avoid those. But try the very smallest size that is left once you throw out all of those orders.






    share|cite|improve this answer






















    • :Thanks for help, am now okay
      – wami.
      Jan 21 '12 at 5:18










    • what about if I consider the Alternating group A4?.
      – wami.
      Jan 21 '12 at 9:01










    • @wami: That's a good place to look, certainly.
      – Arturo Magidin
      Jan 21 '12 at 21:53










    • @ArturoMagidin , may you show plz , why does if the order of the group is a pwoer of a prime then , the converse of lagrange hold ?.the converse hold in the case when , $|G|=pq$, $qleqslant p$ where $q$ doesn't divide $(p-1)$ as $G$ is abelian here , is this what you mean about the holding of the converse when the order is the product of two primes ? what if $q$ divides $p-q$ , does the converse hold ?
      – Fawzy Hegab
      Jun 18 '13 at 5:14













    up vote
    12
    down vote



    accepted







    up vote
    12
    down vote



    accepted






    When you have an implication, "if $P$, then $Q$", the converse is the implication "if $Q$, then $P$."



    Lagrange's Theorem says:




    Let $G$ be finite with $|G|=n$. If $d$ is the order of a subgroup of $G$, then $d$ divides $n$.




    The converse would therefore say:




    Let $G$ be a finite group with $|G|=n$. If $d$ divides $n$, then $d$ is the order of a subgroup of $G$.




    This is an implication. In order to show that an implication is false, you need to show that it is possible for the antecedent ("$d$ divides $n$") to be true and at the same time, the consequence ("$d$ is the order of a subgroup of $H$") to be false.



    So in order to show that the converse of Lagrange's Theorem is not true, what you need to do is:



    1. Exhibit a specific finite group $G$;

    2. Exhibit a specific number $d$ that divides $G$; and

    3. Prove that $G$ does not have any subgroups of order $d$.

    In other words, you need to give an example that shows that the converse statement does not have to be true. (A "counterexample".)



    What you did makes no sense, and does not prove anything. The "converse" has nothing to do with the reciprocal $|H|/|G|$, and is certainly not an assertion that the order of $G$ divides the order of $H$.



    Now, just to help in your search: if $G$ is abelian, then it will satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem, so try looking for nonabelian groups; if $|G|$ is a power of a prime, or the product of two distinct primes, then $G$ will satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem as well, so avoid those. But try the very smallest size that is left once you throw out all of those orders.






    share|cite|improve this answer














    When you have an implication, "if $P$, then $Q$", the converse is the implication "if $Q$, then $P$."



    Lagrange's Theorem says:




    Let $G$ be finite with $|G|=n$. If $d$ is the order of a subgroup of $G$, then $d$ divides $n$.




    The converse would therefore say:




    Let $G$ be a finite group with $|G|=n$. If $d$ divides $n$, then $d$ is the order of a subgroup of $G$.




    This is an implication. In order to show that an implication is false, you need to show that it is possible for the antecedent ("$d$ divides $n$") to be true and at the same time, the consequence ("$d$ is the order of a subgroup of $H$") to be false.



    So in order to show that the converse of Lagrange's Theorem is not true, what you need to do is:



    1. Exhibit a specific finite group $G$;

    2. Exhibit a specific number $d$ that divides $G$; and

    3. Prove that $G$ does not have any subgroups of order $d$.

    In other words, you need to give an example that shows that the converse statement does not have to be true. (A "counterexample".)



    What you did makes no sense, and does not prove anything. The "converse" has nothing to do with the reciprocal $|H|/|G|$, and is certainly not an assertion that the order of $G$ divides the order of $H$.



    Now, just to help in your search: if $G$ is abelian, then it will satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem, so try looking for nonabelian groups; if $|G|$ is a power of a prime, or the product of two distinct primes, then $G$ will satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem as well, so avoid those. But try the very smallest size that is left once you throw out all of those orders.







    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited Jan 21 '12 at 5:06

























    answered Jan 21 '12 at 4:54









    Arturo Magidin

    255k31571890




    255k31571890











    • :Thanks for help, am now okay
      – wami.
      Jan 21 '12 at 5:18










    • what about if I consider the Alternating group A4?.
      – wami.
      Jan 21 '12 at 9:01










    • @wami: That's a good place to look, certainly.
      – Arturo Magidin
      Jan 21 '12 at 21:53










    • @ArturoMagidin , may you show plz , why does if the order of the group is a pwoer of a prime then , the converse of lagrange hold ?.the converse hold in the case when , $|G|=pq$, $qleqslant p$ where $q$ doesn't divide $(p-1)$ as $G$ is abelian here , is this what you mean about the holding of the converse when the order is the product of two primes ? what if $q$ divides $p-q$ , does the converse hold ?
      – Fawzy Hegab
      Jun 18 '13 at 5:14

















    • :Thanks for help, am now okay
      – wami.
      Jan 21 '12 at 5:18










    • what about if I consider the Alternating group A4?.
      – wami.
      Jan 21 '12 at 9:01










    • @wami: That's a good place to look, certainly.
      – Arturo Magidin
      Jan 21 '12 at 21:53










    • @ArturoMagidin , may you show plz , why does if the order of the group is a pwoer of a prime then , the converse of lagrange hold ?.the converse hold in the case when , $|G|=pq$, $qleqslant p$ where $q$ doesn't divide $(p-1)$ as $G$ is abelian here , is this what you mean about the holding of the converse when the order is the product of two primes ? what if $q$ divides $p-q$ , does the converse hold ?
      – Fawzy Hegab
      Jun 18 '13 at 5:14
















    :Thanks for help, am now okay
    – wami.
    Jan 21 '12 at 5:18




    :Thanks for help, am now okay
    – wami.
    Jan 21 '12 at 5:18












    what about if I consider the Alternating group A4?.
    – wami.
    Jan 21 '12 at 9:01




    what about if I consider the Alternating group A4?.
    – wami.
    Jan 21 '12 at 9:01












    @wami: That's a good place to look, certainly.
    – Arturo Magidin
    Jan 21 '12 at 21:53




    @wami: That's a good place to look, certainly.
    – Arturo Magidin
    Jan 21 '12 at 21:53












    @ArturoMagidin , may you show plz , why does if the order of the group is a pwoer of a prime then , the converse of lagrange hold ?.the converse hold in the case when , $|G|=pq$, $qleqslant p$ where $q$ doesn't divide $(p-1)$ as $G$ is abelian here , is this what you mean about the holding of the converse when the order is the product of two primes ? what if $q$ divides $p-q$ , does the converse hold ?
    – Fawzy Hegab
    Jun 18 '13 at 5:14





    @ArturoMagidin , may you show plz , why does if the order of the group is a pwoer of a prime then , the converse of lagrange hold ?.the converse hold in the case when , $|G|=pq$, $qleqslant p$ where $q$ doesn't divide $(p-1)$ as $G$ is abelian here , is this what you mean about the holding of the converse when the order is the product of two primes ? what if $q$ divides $p-q$ , does the converse hold ?
    – Fawzy Hegab
    Jun 18 '13 at 5:14











    up vote
    3
    down vote













    In the positive direction, it is easiest to note that if $G$ is a finite cyclic group of order $n$ and $k$ divides $n$, then $G$ has a subgroup of order $k$. It is generated by $a^n/k$ if $a$ generates $G$. This can be extended to (finite) abelian groups because they are direct sums of cyclic groups.



    Every supersolvable group also satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem, and every group that satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem is solvable. This was shown by Bray in "A note on CLT groups," 1968. Every subgroup and every quotient of a supersolvable group is supersolvable, hence satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem.



    As Arturo noted, standard results of group theory show that there can be no counterexample whose order is a power of a prime or a product of two distinct primes. But there are other numbers, like $20=2^2cdot 5$, for which every group with that number of elements satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem. There have been several articles written both on the possible orders of groups that don't satisfy the converse as well as other properties of such groups. One example is a result of Struik in "Partial converses to Lagrange's theorem,", 1978. To quote part of the review by Humphreys (because I don't have the article):




    Let $p$ and $q$ be distinct primes with $p$ not dividing $q-1$ and $q$ not dividing $p-1$. Let $e$ be the exponent of $p textmod,q$ and $f$ be the exponent of $q textmod,p$. Then $p^aq^b$ is a CLT number if and only if one of the following four conditions is satisfied: (i) $a<e$ and $b<f$; (ii) $e$ is odd, $a=2e-1$ and $b<f$; (iii) $f$ is odd, $b=2f-1$ and $a<e$; (iv) $e$ and $f$ are both odd, $a=2e-1$ and $b=2f-1$.




    For example, if $p=3$ and $q=5$, then $e=4$ and $f=2$, so by part (i) we see that every group of order $45=3^2cdot 5$ or $135=3^3cdot 5$ satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem. It is known (as seen for example in Curran's "Non-CLT groups of small order" where such groups are studied) that the numbers less than $100$ that are orders of groups that don't satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem are the following: $12,24,36,48,56,60,72,75,80,84$ and $96$.



    (I didn't know any of the results from these articles, but I searched because the question made me interested.)






    share|cite|improve this answer


















    • 1




      See also this question and this one.
      – Arturo Magidin
      Jan 21 '12 at 22:42










    • @Arturo: Thanks very much, I hadn't seen those.
      – Jonas Meyer
      Jan 21 '12 at 22:57














    up vote
    3
    down vote













    In the positive direction, it is easiest to note that if $G$ is a finite cyclic group of order $n$ and $k$ divides $n$, then $G$ has a subgroup of order $k$. It is generated by $a^n/k$ if $a$ generates $G$. This can be extended to (finite) abelian groups because they are direct sums of cyclic groups.



    Every supersolvable group also satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem, and every group that satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem is solvable. This was shown by Bray in "A note on CLT groups," 1968. Every subgroup and every quotient of a supersolvable group is supersolvable, hence satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem.



    As Arturo noted, standard results of group theory show that there can be no counterexample whose order is a power of a prime or a product of two distinct primes. But there are other numbers, like $20=2^2cdot 5$, for which every group with that number of elements satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem. There have been several articles written both on the possible orders of groups that don't satisfy the converse as well as other properties of such groups. One example is a result of Struik in "Partial converses to Lagrange's theorem,", 1978. To quote part of the review by Humphreys (because I don't have the article):




    Let $p$ and $q$ be distinct primes with $p$ not dividing $q-1$ and $q$ not dividing $p-1$. Let $e$ be the exponent of $p textmod,q$ and $f$ be the exponent of $q textmod,p$. Then $p^aq^b$ is a CLT number if and only if one of the following four conditions is satisfied: (i) $a<e$ and $b<f$; (ii) $e$ is odd, $a=2e-1$ and $b<f$; (iii) $f$ is odd, $b=2f-1$ and $a<e$; (iv) $e$ and $f$ are both odd, $a=2e-1$ and $b=2f-1$.




    For example, if $p=3$ and $q=5$, then $e=4$ and $f=2$, so by part (i) we see that every group of order $45=3^2cdot 5$ or $135=3^3cdot 5$ satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem. It is known (as seen for example in Curran's "Non-CLT groups of small order" where such groups are studied) that the numbers less than $100$ that are orders of groups that don't satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem are the following: $12,24,36,48,56,60,72,75,80,84$ and $96$.



    (I didn't know any of the results from these articles, but I searched because the question made me interested.)






    share|cite|improve this answer


















    • 1




      See also this question and this one.
      – Arturo Magidin
      Jan 21 '12 at 22:42










    • @Arturo: Thanks very much, I hadn't seen those.
      – Jonas Meyer
      Jan 21 '12 at 22:57












    up vote
    3
    down vote










    up vote
    3
    down vote









    In the positive direction, it is easiest to note that if $G$ is a finite cyclic group of order $n$ and $k$ divides $n$, then $G$ has a subgroup of order $k$. It is generated by $a^n/k$ if $a$ generates $G$. This can be extended to (finite) abelian groups because they are direct sums of cyclic groups.



    Every supersolvable group also satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem, and every group that satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem is solvable. This was shown by Bray in "A note on CLT groups," 1968. Every subgroup and every quotient of a supersolvable group is supersolvable, hence satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem.



    As Arturo noted, standard results of group theory show that there can be no counterexample whose order is a power of a prime or a product of two distinct primes. But there are other numbers, like $20=2^2cdot 5$, for which every group with that number of elements satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem. There have been several articles written both on the possible orders of groups that don't satisfy the converse as well as other properties of such groups. One example is a result of Struik in "Partial converses to Lagrange's theorem,", 1978. To quote part of the review by Humphreys (because I don't have the article):




    Let $p$ and $q$ be distinct primes with $p$ not dividing $q-1$ and $q$ not dividing $p-1$. Let $e$ be the exponent of $p textmod,q$ and $f$ be the exponent of $q textmod,p$. Then $p^aq^b$ is a CLT number if and only if one of the following four conditions is satisfied: (i) $a<e$ and $b<f$; (ii) $e$ is odd, $a=2e-1$ and $b<f$; (iii) $f$ is odd, $b=2f-1$ and $a<e$; (iv) $e$ and $f$ are both odd, $a=2e-1$ and $b=2f-1$.




    For example, if $p=3$ and $q=5$, then $e=4$ and $f=2$, so by part (i) we see that every group of order $45=3^2cdot 5$ or $135=3^3cdot 5$ satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem. It is known (as seen for example in Curran's "Non-CLT groups of small order" where such groups are studied) that the numbers less than $100$ that are orders of groups that don't satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem are the following: $12,24,36,48,56,60,72,75,80,84$ and $96$.



    (I didn't know any of the results from these articles, but I searched because the question made me interested.)






    share|cite|improve this answer














    In the positive direction, it is easiest to note that if $G$ is a finite cyclic group of order $n$ and $k$ divides $n$, then $G$ has a subgroup of order $k$. It is generated by $a^n/k$ if $a$ generates $G$. This can be extended to (finite) abelian groups because they are direct sums of cyclic groups.



    Every supersolvable group also satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem, and every group that satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem is solvable. This was shown by Bray in "A note on CLT groups," 1968. Every subgroup and every quotient of a supersolvable group is supersolvable, hence satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem.



    As Arturo noted, standard results of group theory show that there can be no counterexample whose order is a power of a prime or a product of two distinct primes. But there are other numbers, like $20=2^2cdot 5$, for which every group with that number of elements satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem. There have been several articles written both on the possible orders of groups that don't satisfy the converse as well as other properties of such groups. One example is a result of Struik in "Partial converses to Lagrange's theorem,", 1978. To quote part of the review by Humphreys (because I don't have the article):




    Let $p$ and $q$ be distinct primes with $p$ not dividing $q-1$ and $q$ not dividing $p-1$. Let $e$ be the exponent of $p textmod,q$ and $f$ be the exponent of $q textmod,p$. Then $p^aq^b$ is a CLT number if and only if one of the following four conditions is satisfied: (i) $a<e$ and $b<f$; (ii) $e$ is odd, $a=2e-1$ and $b<f$; (iii) $f$ is odd, $b=2f-1$ and $a<e$; (iv) $e$ and $f$ are both odd, $a=2e-1$ and $b=2f-1$.




    For example, if $p=3$ and $q=5$, then $e=4$ and $f=2$, so by part (i) we see that every group of order $45=3^2cdot 5$ or $135=3^3cdot 5$ satisfies the converse of Lagrange's Theorem. It is known (as seen for example in Curran's "Non-CLT groups of small order" where such groups are studied) that the numbers less than $100$ that are orders of groups that don't satisfy the converse of Lagrange's Theorem are the following: $12,24,36,48,56,60,72,75,80,84$ and $96$.



    (I didn't know any of the results from these articles, but I searched because the question made me interested.)







    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited Jan 21 '12 at 7:36

























    answered Jan 21 '12 at 4:53









    Jonas Meyer

    39.2k6142248




    39.2k6142248







    • 1




      See also this question and this one.
      – Arturo Magidin
      Jan 21 '12 at 22:42










    • @Arturo: Thanks very much, I hadn't seen those.
      – Jonas Meyer
      Jan 21 '12 at 22:57












    • 1




      See also this question and this one.
      – Arturo Magidin
      Jan 21 '12 at 22:42










    • @Arturo: Thanks very much, I hadn't seen those.
      – Jonas Meyer
      Jan 21 '12 at 22:57







    1




    1




    See also this question and this one.
    – Arturo Magidin
    Jan 21 '12 at 22:42




    See also this question and this one.
    – Arturo Magidin
    Jan 21 '12 at 22:42












    @Arturo: Thanks very much, I hadn't seen those.
    – Jonas Meyer
    Jan 21 '12 at 22:57




    @Arturo: Thanks very much, I hadn't seen those.
    – Jonas Meyer
    Jan 21 '12 at 22:57










    up vote
    0
    down vote













    What the converse of a theorem is depends on exactly how it is formulated, and in the formulation you gave there is no converse. As Arturo said you need a statement of the form "if $P$ then $Q$" to turn into the converse "if $Q$ then $P$" (or if you prefer "if not $P$ then not $Q$, which is logically equivalent). However your statement does not contain the word "if", so strictly speaking there is no converse.



    Arturo gave an equivalent statement that does contain the word "if", and proved that the converse to that statement is false. However his formulation is rather distant from yours, notably he introduces $d$ that is not mentioned in your statement at all (and the mention of $H$ is dropped). A closer approximation would be the formulation "Let $G$ be a finite group. If $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, then the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$". The converse of this statement is "Let $G$ be a finite group. If the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$, then $H$ is a subgroup of $G$". The problem with this statement is that $H$ now comes out of the blue; since we have to prove that $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, we may not assume that in interpreting the "if" part, and we have the problem that, without any assumption on $H$, the phrase "the order of $H$" makes no sense. So with this approach there is still no sensible converse to prove. A solution would be to expand "the order of $H$" to "the number of elements of $H$", which makes sense whenever $H$ is a set. If we add a clause stipulating that before the "if", we get as original statement "Let $G$ be a finite group and $H$ a set. If $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, then the number of elements of $H$ divides the order of $G$", which has a sensible (but clearly false) converse "Let $G$ be a finite group and $H$ a set. If the number of elements of $H$ divides the order of $G$, then $H$ is a subgroup of $G$." I'm sure you are able to find counterexamples to the latter statement easily.



    The morale of the story is that "the converse" of an arbitrary statement is not well defined, and if it is, it could be nonsensical; even if the converse makes, the converse of a different but equivalent formulation of the same fact could be inequivalent to the original converse, and one can imagine one of them being true and another false. In the current case we have not found any "converse" that is actually true, but as an exercise you may try to find one... (A somewhat cheating trivial solution to this exercise is that, being a proven statement, Lagrange's Theorem is formally equivalent to every other proven statement, in the sense that assuming one of them you can prove the other. Now choose any proven statement whose converse happens to be proven as well.)






    share|cite|improve this answer
























      up vote
      0
      down vote













      What the converse of a theorem is depends on exactly how it is formulated, and in the formulation you gave there is no converse. As Arturo said you need a statement of the form "if $P$ then $Q$" to turn into the converse "if $Q$ then $P$" (or if you prefer "if not $P$ then not $Q$, which is logically equivalent). However your statement does not contain the word "if", so strictly speaking there is no converse.



      Arturo gave an equivalent statement that does contain the word "if", and proved that the converse to that statement is false. However his formulation is rather distant from yours, notably he introduces $d$ that is not mentioned in your statement at all (and the mention of $H$ is dropped). A closer approximation would be the formulation "Let $G$ be a finite group. If $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, then the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$". The converse of this statement is "Let $G$ be a finite group. If the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$, then $H$ is a subgroup of $G$". The problem with this statement is that $H$ now comes out of the blue; since we have to prove that $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, we may not assume that in interpreting the "if" part, and we have the problem that, without any assumption on $H$, the phrase "the order of $H$" makes no sense. So with this approach there is still no sensible converse to prove. A solution would be to expand "the order of $H$" to "the number of elements of $H$", which makes sense whenever $H$ is a set. If we add a clause stipulating that before the "if", we get as original statement "Let $G$ be a finite group and $H$ a set. If $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, then the number of elements of $H$ divides the order of $G$", which has a sensible (but clearly false) converse "Let $G$ be a finite group and $H$ a set. If the number of elements of $H$ divides the order of $G$, then $H$ is a subgroup of $G$." I'm sure you are able to find counterexamples to the latter statement easily.



      The morale of the story is that "the converse" of an arbitrary statement is not well defined, and if it is, it could be nonsensical; even if the converse makes, the converse of a different but equivalent formulation of the same fact could be inequivalent to the original converse, and one can imagine one of them being true and another false. In the current case we have not found any "converse" that is actually true, but as an exercise you may try to find one... (A somewhat cheating trivial solution to this exercise is that, being a proven statement, Lagrange's Theorem is formally equivalent to every other proven statement, in the sense that assuming one of them you can prove the other. Now choose any proven statement whose converse happens to be proven as well.)






      share|cite|improve this answer






















        up vote
        0
        down vote










        up vote
        0
        down vote









        What the converse of a theorem is depends on exactly how it is formulated, and in the formulation you gave there is no converse. As Arturo said you need a statement of the form "if $P$ then $Q$" to turn into the converse "if $Q$ then $P$" (or if you prefer "if not $P$ then not $Q$, which is logically equivalent). However your statement does not contain the word "if", so strictly speaking there is no converse.



        Arturo gave an equivalent statement that does contain the word "if", and proved that the converse to that statement is false. However his formulation is rather distant from yours, notably he introduces $d$ that is not mentioned in your statement at all (and the mention of $H$ is dropped). A closer approximation would be the formulation "Let $G$ be a finite group. If $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, then the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$". The converse of this statement is "Let $G$ be a finite group. If the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$, then $H$ is a subgroup of $G$". The problem with this statement is that $H$ now comes out of the blue; since we have to prove that $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, we may not assume that in interpreting the "if" part, and we have the problem that, without any assumption on $H$, the phrase "the order of $H$" makes no sense. So with this approach there is still no sensible converse to prove. A solution would be to expand "the order of $H$" to "the number of elements of $H$", which makes sense whenever $H$ is a set. If we add a clause stipulating that before the "if", we get as original statement "Let $G$ be a finite group and $H$ a set. If $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, then the number of elements of $H$ divides the order of $G$", which has a sensible (but clearly false) converse "Let $G$ be a finite group and $H$ a set. If the number of elements of $H$ divides the order of $G$, then $H$ is a subgroup of $G$." I'm sure you are able to find counterexamples to the latter statement easily.



        The morale of the story is that "the converse" of an arbitrary statement is not well defined, and if it is, it could be nonsensical; even if the converse makes, the converse of a different but equivalent formulation of the same fact could be inequivalent to the original converse, and one can imagine one of them being true and another false. In the current case we have not found any "converse" that is actually true, but as an exercise you may try to find one... (A somewhat cheating trivial solution to this exercise is that, being a proven statement, Lagrange's Theorem is formally equivalent to every other proven statement, in the sense that assuming one of them you can prove the other. Now choose any proven statement whose converse happens to be proven as well.)






        share|cite|improve this answer












        What the converse of a theorem is depends on exactly how it is formulated, and in the formulation you gave there is no converse. As Arturo said you need a statement of the form "if $P$ then $Q$" to turn into the converse "if $Q$ then $P$" (or if you prefer "if not $P$ then not $Q$, which is logically equivalent). However your statement does not contain the word "if", so strictly speaking there is no converse.



        Arturo gave an equivalent statement that does contain the word "if", and proved that the converse to that statement is false. However his formulation is rather distant from yours, notably he introduces $d$ that is not mentioned in your statement at all (and the mention of $H$ is dropped). A closer approximation would be the formulation "Let $G$ be a finite group. If $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, then the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$". The converse of this statement is "Let $G$ be a finite group. If the order of $H$ divides the order of $G$, then $H$ is a subgroup of $G$". The problem with this statement is that $H$ now comes out of the blue; since we have to prove that $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, we may not assume that in interpreting the "if" part, and we have the problem that, without any assumption on $H$, the phrase "the order of $H$" makes no sense. So with this approach there is still no sensible converse to prove. A solution would be to expand "the order of $H$" to "the number of elements of $H$", which makes sense whenever $H$ is a set. If we add a clause stipulating that before the "if", we get as original statement "Let $G$ be a finite group and $H$ a set. If $H$ is a subgroup of $G$, then the number of elements of $H$ divides the order of $G$", which has a sensible (but clearly false) converse "Let $G$ be a finite group and $H$ a set. If the number of elements of $H$ divides the order of $G$, then $H$ is a subgroup of $G$." I'm sure you are able to find counterexamples to the latter statement easily.



        The morale of the story is that "the converse" of an arbitrary statement is not well defined, and if it is, it could be nonsensical; even if the converse makes, the converse of a different but equivalent formulation of the same fact could be inequivalent to the original converse, and one can imagine one of them being true and another false. In the current case we have not found any "converse" that is actually true, but as an exercise you may try to find one... (A somewhat cheating trivial solution to this exercise is that, being a proven statement, Lagrange's Theorem is formally equivalent to every other proven statement, in the sense that assuming one of them you can prove the other. Now choose any proven statement whose converse happens to be proven as well.)







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered Jan 21 '12 at 10:28









        Marc van Leeuwen

        85.1k5100213




        85.1k5100213




















            up vote
            -1
            down vote













            Lagranges theorem



            $$H<G---->|G|/|H|$$



            the converse says



            $$|G|/|H|----->H<G$$



            And the converse is not true, because A4 is a counter example and A4 is a group of oder 12 having no subgroup of order 6.



            Proof:



            A4 contains eight 3 cycles of the form (abc) and three pairs of disjoint transposition of the form (ab)(cd) and an identity element where a, b, c, d are disjoint elements.



            If a sub group contains 3 cycles (abc) it must also contain it's inverse (acb).



            If a sub group of order 6 exists then it must contain an identity element, a pair of transposition because the odd number of non identity elements cannot just be 3cycles (abc) and their inverses.



            If A4 contains a sub group of order 6 it must contain at least two pairs of transposition because A4 contains only four elements that are not 3cycles.



            And so without loss of generality:



            Suppose the sub group of order 6 contains (abc) it must also contain(acb) it's inverse and since it contains a pair of transposition (ab)(cd) such that when we multiply the group is closed so (abc) (ab)(cd)=(bdc).



            The inverse of (bdc)=(bcd)



            (ab)(cd)(abc)=(acd)



            (acd)invesre =(adc)



            And then the identity elements which all together makes up more than 6 elements and so A4 has no subgroup of order 6.






            share|cite|improve this answer






















            • Your answer did not get formatted right. COuld you please edit it?
              – Cornman
              Aug 27 at 1:08














            up vote
            -1
            down vote













            Lagranges theorem



            $$H<G---->|G|/|H|$$



            the converse says



            $$|G|/|H|----->H<G$$



            And the converse is not true, because A4 is a counter example and A4 is a group of oder 12 having no subgroup of order 6.



            Proof:



            A4 contains eight 3 cycles of the form (abc) and three pairs of disjoint transposition of the form (ab)(cd) and an identity element where a, b, c, d are disjoint elements.



            If a sub group contains 3 cycles (abc) it must also contain it's inverse (acb).



            If a sub group of order 6 exists then it must contain an identity element, a pair of transposition because the odd number of non identity elements cannot just be 3cycles (abc) and their inverses.



            If A4 contains a sub group of order 6 it must contain at least two pairs of transposition because A4 contains only four elements that are not 3cycles.



            And so without loss of generality:



            Suppose the sub group of order 6 contains (abc) it must also contain(acb) it's inverse and since it contains a pair of transposition (ab)(cd) such that when we multiply the group is closed so (abc) (ab)(cd)=(bdc).



            The inverse of (bdc)=(bcd)



            (ab)(cd)(abc)=(acd)



            (acd)invesre =(adc)



            And then the identity elements which all together makes up more than 6 elements and so A4 has no subgroup of order 6.






            share|cite|improve this answer






















            • Your answer did not get formatted right. COuld you please edit it?
              – Cornman
              Aug 27 at 1:08












            up vote
            -1
            down vote










            up vote
            -1
            down vote









            Lagranges theorem



            $$H<G---->|G|/|H|$$



            the converse says



            $$|G|/|H|----->H<G$$



            And the converse is not true, because A4 is a counter example and A4 is a group of oder 12 having no subgroup of order 6.



            Proof:



            A4 contains eight 3 cycles of the form (abc) and three pairs of disjoint transposition of the form (ab)(cd) and an identity element where a, b, c, d are disjoint elements.



            If a sub group contains 3 cycles (abc) it must also contain it's inverse (acb).



            If a sub group of order 6 exists then it must contain an identity element, a pair of transposition because the odd number of non identity elements cannot just be 3cycles (abc) and their inverses.



            If A4 contains a sub group of order 6 it must contain at least two pairs of transposition because A4 contains only four elements that are not 3cycles.



            And so without loss of generality:



            Suppose the sub group of order 6 contains (abc) it must also contain(acb) it's inverse and since it contains a pair of transposition (ab)(cd) such that when we multiply the group is closed so (abc) (ab)(cd)=(bdc).



            The inverse of (bdc)=(bcd)



            (ab)(cd)(abc)=(acd)



            (acd)invesre =(adc)



            And then the identity elements which all together makes up more than 6 elements and so A4 has no subgroup of order 6.






            share|cite|improve this answer














            Lagranges theorem



            $$H<G---->|G|/|H|$$



            the converse says



            $$|G|/|H|----->H<G$$



            And the converse is not true, because A4 is a counter example and A4 is a group of oder 12 having no subgroup of order 6.



            Proof:



            A4 contains eight 3 cycles of the form (abc) and three pairs of disjoint transposition of the form (ab)(cd) and an identity element where a, b, c, d are disjoint elements.



            If a sub group contains 3 cycles (abc) it must also contain it's inverse (acb).



            If a sub group of order 6 exists then it must contain an identity element, a pair of transposition because the odd number of non identity elements cannot just be 3cycles (abc) and their inverses.



            If A4 contains a sub group of order 6 it must contain at least two pairs of transposition because A4 contains only four elements that are not 3cycles.



            And so without loss of generality:



            Suppose the sub group of order 6 contains (abc) it must also contain(acb) it's inverse and since it contains a pair of transposition (ab)(cd) such that when we multiply the group is closed so (abc) (ab)(cd)=(bdc).



            The inverse of (bdc)=(bcd)



            (ab)(cd)(abc)=(acd)



            (acd)invesre =(adc)



            And then the identity elements which all together makes up more than 6 elements and so A4 has no subgroup of order 6.







            share|cite|improve this answer














            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer








            edited Aug 27 at 1:11









            peterh

            2,15441631




            2,15441631










            answered Aug 27 at 0:10









            Makinde David

            1




            1











            • Your answer did not get formatted right. COuld you please edit it?
              – Cornman
              Aug 27 at 1:08
















            • Your answer did not get formatted right. COuld you please edit it?
              – Cornman
              Aug 27 at 1:08















            Your answer did not get formatted right. COuld you please edit it?
            – Cornman
            Aug 27 at 1:08




            Your answer did not get formatted right. COuld you please edit it?
            – Cornman
            Aug 27 at 1:08

















             

            draft saved


            draft discarded















































             


            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function ()
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f100933%2fhow-to-prove-that-the-converse-of-lagranges-theorem-is-not-true%23new-answer', 'question_page');

            );

            Post as a guest













































































            這個網誌中的熱門文章

            How to combine Bézier curves to a surface?

            Why am i infinitely getting the same tweet with the Twitter Search API?

            Carbon dioxide